The Morality and Law Relationship Essay

  • To find inspiration for your paper and overcome writer’s block
  • As a source of information (ensure proper referencing)
  • As a template for you assignment

Introduction

Changes in law created by moral concerns, reference list.

Moral principles are the backbone of society. In the process of establishing rules and hierarchies to follow, people have chosen certain principles and beliefs that are beneficial to them as a group. Common taboos such as killing or stealing are understood as detrimental to social life, creating an incentive to prevent people from committing them. Similarly, nations create and uphold laws in order to reach specific goals or prevent unwanted outcomes. There is a direct link between what society understands as valuable, morally and ethically, and legislation. With the evolution of human thought, the law changed accordingly, following certain precedents or exchanging them for newer ones.

While it is impossible for established law to account for any moral dilemma, the commonly understood boundaries of right and wrong can often be supported by existing legislation. This paper is concerned with discussing and showcasing the direct link between moral issues and legality. Using examples from the past, including case law and historical events, it will be possible to approach this subject. In particular, topics of international workers’ rights and racial segregation will be broached, as their legal status has shifted along with the people’s moral values.

Worker Rights

Throughout history, work has always been a part of people’s lives. An activity directed at securing a living, creating certain outcomes that are necessary for human prosperity. With the transition from feudal to capital societies, work became vital in producing goods and services. Without labor, it is impossible to support the economy, maintain a capitalist framework and fulfill the needs of consumers. Workers as a central force in promoting the necessary outcomes for society as a whole. Due to the existence of a profit motive, and a lack of regulation in early capitalism, emerging factories rarely had workplace regulations or protections for their laborers. For many, this resulted in trauma, injury, and death in the workplace. People were overworked in unsafe conditions for meager pay, forced into the production cycle that regarded them as simple cogs in the machine.

The mistreatment of workers contributed to the emergence of worker’s rights organizations, which argued against unethical and immoral workplace treatment of employees. Different nations have had their own distinct relationships with the concept of workplace advocacy, depending on their history or leadership. However, the vast majority of nations have been able to enact labor laws in a certain capacity. Social movements, protests, sit-ins, and active participation of workers all across the world were effective in highlighting the moral reprehensibility of contemporary professional practices. Most worker’s rights organizations found the existing lack of protections or considerations for the working class intolerable and focused on helping the common people. They argued that individuals have to be treated with dignity and fairness, considering their worth and individual humans and their needs. This is especially true of considerations such as child labor, unreasonably long work hours, or a lack of days off. In the US, a combination of factory owner neglect and a desire to maximize profits drove factories to ignore the moral and ethical concerns of their workers. The Fair Labor Standards Act, introduced in 1938, established regulations for acceptable work hours, pay, and days off and fully prohibited child labor (Fair Labor Standards Act of 1938). The incessant work of activists and worker’s interest groups has forced changes in the government, which recognized the unethical nature of harsh business practices. Other nations were similarly capable of negotiating fairer labor standards. In France, the Matignon Agreements of 1936 established a regulated work week, labor protections, and minimum wage. For UK workers, the 1998 National Minimum Wage Act was a notable legislative change, giving all employees more livable and secure wages. The collective work of governments and their people was able to make labor practices align better with the social and moral standards of today’s age.

Segregation and Massive Resistance in the US

Segregation is another major consideration for the United States of America, one connected with its storied legacy of slavery. Even after slaves were legally freed, black people were largely unable to enjoy the same rights and capabilities as their white counterparts. Local governments, businesses and various entities worked to dictate where the black population could live, study, and even eat. Certain states used their authority to force the newly freed slaves into a system of suppression and exploitation. In the state of Virginia, for example, the local constitution of the time focused heavily on reinforcing the principles of white supremacy and black subjugation. In particular, black people were largely excluded from voting, disallowing them from shaping the future of their community. Similarly, all-black schools received limited funding, and African-Americans were often forced to live in poorer areas. The combination of existing law and a lack of protection contributed to a systematic disparity between the black and white populations.

Despite established laws and protections against segregation existing in the US Constitution, states were able to exercise their own authority in order to reinforce certain outcomes. However, considerable public pushback could also be felt, both from the legal and ethical side of the issue. With the precedent set by the Brown v. Board of Education case, other courts and public figures argued on the unconstitutional nature of segregation. Public figures in newspapers, such as Lenoir Chambers of The Virginian-Pilot, worked tirelessly to convince the public about the immoral nature of segregation. The efforts of black activist groups, good-faith politicians, and courts have laid a path forward to fighting the remains of segregation in the US. This has resulted in other precedent court cases, such as the one discussed in Harrison’s contemporary article. The writing talks about the Court for the Eastern District of Virginia’s decision to rule desegregation as unconstitutional, which signaled a major shift in legal and public opinion within Virginia. The existence of an active conversation has helped the courts to take matters to the legal level and support vulnerable individuals.

The examination of these two subjects has presented an important connection between legislation, people’s rights, and morality. In the course of history, people that cared about the lives and health of others wanted to see positive change which reflected the value of human life have prompted changes in legislation. Considerations of ethics and morality of people’s treatment coincided with the need to protect certain groups, allowing the law to change. Workers demanded to be treated with dignity and understanding that was warranted by their importance, prompting the government to introduce better labor standards. Similarly, activists and public media figures fought against segregation and opposed attempts at re-introducing it in society. Their concerns and passion, often focused on the well-being and security of others, were rooted in what they understood as right for society. People who want to see their community better reflect individual-centered moral considerations are largely responsible for shaping today’s legislation.

Crawford, Jason. “How Factories Were Made Safe.” The Roots of Progress .

Daugherity, Brian. “Desegregation in Public Schools.” Encyclopedia Virginia .

Harrison, Joseph. “Virginia’s ‘Massive Resistance’ Laws Declared Unconstitutional.” The Journal of Negro Education 28, no. 2 (1959): 163.

Hayter, Susan, and International Labour Office. The Role of Collective Bargaining in the Global Economy: Negotiating for Social Justice . Cheltenham, UK; Northampton, Ma: Edward Elgar; Geneva, Switzerland, 2011.

Lebowitz, Shana. “Here’s How the 40-Hour Workweek Became the Standard in America – Business Insider.” Business Insider . Business Insider, 2015.

Leidholdt, Alex. Standing before the Shouting Mob Lenoir Chambers and Virginia’s Massive Resistance to Public School Integration. Univ Of Alabama Pr, 2007.

Queen Mary University of London. “A Short History of the Living Wage in the UK.” Www.qmul.ac.uk .

Ralph Clipman Mcdanel. The Virginia Constitutional Convention of 1901-1902 . Holmes Beach, Fl: Gaunt, 1999.

Fair Labor Standards Act of 1938 [Online]. U.S. Department of Labor Wage and Hour Division.

Brown v. Board of Education of Topeka [1954] 347 U.S. 483 (U.S. Supreme Court).

  • Additional Support Needs of Vulnerable Groups
  • Ethical Obligations in Criminal Justice
  • Crime in Virginia: Nature and Trends
  • Differences in Taxation Between Florida and Virginia State
  • Lawyers' Professional Responsibility and Regulation
  • Bribery in the Pirates of Penzance Company
  • Ethics of Racial Profiling in the United States
  • Law and Morality Separation and Relationship
  • Food Lion, Inc. v. ABC, Inc.- 194 F.3d 505
  • Aspects of Ethics in Policing
  • Chicago (A-D)
  • Chicago (N-B)

IvyPanda. (2023, June 19). The Morality and Law Relationship. https://ivypanda.com/essays/the-morality-and-law-relationship/

"The Morality and Law Relationship." IvyPanda , 19 June 2023, ivypanda.com/essays/the-morality-and-law-relationship/.

IvyPanda . (2023) 'The Morality and Law Relationship'. 19 June.

IvyPanda . 2023. "The Morality and Law Relationship." June 19, 2023. https://ivypanda.com/essays/the-morality-and-law-relationship/.

1. IvyPanda . "The Morality and Law Relationship." June 19, 2023. https://ivypanda.com/essays/the-morality-and-law-relationship/.

Bibliography

IvyPanda . "The Morality and Law Relationship." June 19, 2023. https://ivypanda.com/essays/the-morality-and-law-relationship/.

Scholarship Archive

  • < Previous

Home > Faculty Publications > Faculty Books > 251

Faculty Books

The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality

The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality

Joseph Raz , Columbia Law School Follow

Publication Date

https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198253457.001.0001

Description

This classic collection of essays, first published in 1979, has had an enduring influence on philosophical work on the nature of law and its relation to morality. Raz begins by presenting an analysis of the concept of authority and what is involved in law's claim to moral authority. He then develops a detailed explanation of the nature of law and legal systems, presenting a seminal argument for legal positivism. Within this framework Raz then examines the areas of legal thought that have been viewed as impregnated with moral values – namely the social functions of law, the ideal of the rule of law, and the adjudicative role of the courts.

The final part of the book is given to understanding the proper moral attitude of a citizen towards the law. Raz examines whether the citizen is under a moral obligation to obey the law and whether there is a right to dissent. Two appendices, added for the revised edition, develop Raz's views on the nature of law, offering a further dialogue with the work of Hans Kelsen, and a reply to Robert Alexy's criticisms of legal positivism.

This revised edition makes accessible one of the classic works of modern legal philosophy, and represents an ideal companion to Raz's new collection, Between Authority and Interpretation .

Disciplines

Jurisprudence | Law | Law and Philosophy | Legal Ethics and Professional Responsibility

9780199573561

Oxford University Press

New York, NY

The 1st edition (1979) of this title is available as an eBook through the Columbia University Libraries.

Recommended Citation

Raz, Joseph, "The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality" (2009). Faculty Books . 251. https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/books/251

Find in Library

Find in WorldCat

Since June 24, 2020

Advanced Search

  • Notify me via email or RSS

Columbia Law Links

  • Columbia Law School
  • Faculty Directory
  • Research Centers & Programs
  • Student Journals
  • Student Organizations
  • Columbia Law Library
  • Collections
  • All Disciplines
  • Law Disciplines
  • All Authors
  • Columbia Law Authors

Author Corner

Home | About | FAQ | My Account | Accessibility Statement

Privacy Copyright

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

The Limits of Law

A central—perhaps the central—question of the philosophy of law concerns the relationship between law and morality. The concern breaks down into many issues, both conceptual and evaluative. Among the evaluative issues is the question of obedience to law: does the fact that some norm is a legal norm provide any reason to obey it? (Green 2004 [2012]; Delmas & Brownlee 2021). By contrast, conceptual or analytical issues include the identification of conditions necessary for the existence of a legal system, irrespective of the system’s goodness or otherwise. Must some reference to morality enter into an adequate definition of law or legal system? (Hart 1963 [1982]; Dickson 2012). And so on.

The present topic, the question of the limits of law, is widely understood to be one of the important evaluative questions, revolving around the legal enforcement of morality. In the nineteenth century John Stuart Mill proposed “the harm principle” as his answer; in the late twentieth century H.L.A Hart adopted a significantly modified version of Mill’s principle and further important versions of the harm principle followed in the hands of Joel Feinberg and Joseph Raz (Sections 4–6 below). The harm principle in all its manifestations has encountered strong resistance, most notably from “legal moralists” (Sections 1–3) and remains in the eyes of many the focus of debate, the view to adopt, supplement or modify (as some would say), or to beat and replace (as others would say).

A more recent strand to the question of the legal enforcement of morality is Rawlsian in origin, most notably the claim that constitutional essentials and matters of basic justice should be subject to a constraint of public reason (Section 7). An alternative perspective challenges the assumption that the limits of law is simply an evaluative question focussed on law as a neutral instrument put to good ends and bad. It takes the limits of law as in part a conceptual question. Law of its nature has an internal morality of its own, so it is claimed, with its own built-in limits (Section 8). A further question relates to the deployment by the law of techniques beyond coercion (Section 8).

1. Legal Moralism: Formulation and Structure

2.1 privacy, 2.2 liberty, 2.3 the crime tariff, 2.4 self-defeat and other forms of defeat, 3. the morality of legal moralism, 4. the harm principle, 5.1 other-regarding conduct, 5.2 a setback to interests, 5.3 a setback to autonomy/prospect harm, 6.1 utilitarian/consequentialist foundations, 6.2 perfectionist/value-pluralist foundations, 7. public reason, 8. other directions: legality, a “modal kind” and coercion, 9. conclusion, other internet resources, related entries.

Legal moralism is an initially simple and natural position to take in delineating the legitimate boundaries of the legal use of coercion. At its heart is a strong link between moral wrongdoing and legal (especially criminal) wrongdoing. In the 1960s Herbert Hart applied the label “legal moralist” to his intellectual sparring partner, Lord Patrick Devlin, and the label stuck (Hart 1963; Devlin 1965). Devlin’s account, which we come to below, has led to numerous responses; beyond Hart himself a sample might include: Rostow (1960), Ronald Dworkin (1965), Ten (1972), Feinberg (1987), Kane (1994), Jeffrie Murphy (1999), Gerald Dworkin (1999), Kekes (2000), Nussbaum (2004, 2010), Wall (2013). While many of the responses to Devlin have been heavily critical, the approach is alive and well and continues to develop in the hands, among others, of self-declared legal moralists, such as Michael Moore and Antony Duff (Duff 2016: 96, 2018; Moore 1997, 2014) and in writers who seem at least broadly favourably disposed (Tadros 2016a: 169–170). Something akin to it is also found implicit in a vast range of legal writing.

Legal Moralism is often formulated in terms of immorality as a sufficient condition for legal coercion. Hart asks whether the fact that conduct is immoral is “sufficient to justify making that conduct punishable by law?” (Hart 1963 [1982:4]). Larry Alexander similarly defines legal moralism as “the position that immorality is sufficient for criminalization” (Alexander 2003: 131). Joel Feinberg—mindful of the possibility that a legal moralist might want to excise from the picture certain kinds of immorality—defines legal moralism without mention of sufficient conditions:

it can be morally legitimate to prohibit conduct on the ground that it is inherently immoral, even though it causes neither harm nor offence to the actor or to others. (Feinberg 1984: 27, emphasis added)

However, Hart’s and Alexander’s formulations are at best misleading as characterizations of legal moralism; [ 1 ] and Feinberg’s is incomplete by the measure of his own formulations of rival positions. What both leave out is the important point that immorality or wrongdoing is generally taken by legal moralists to be a prima facie or pro tanto ground for the imposition of legal coercion, subject to potential defeat by other factors. [ 2 ] That certain conduct is by common standards immoral gives the society, in Devlin’s view, “prima facie right to legislate” (Devlin 1965: 11). The immorality is certainly a valid reason for criminalization, but such a reason will fail to be conclusive if unable to override a series of potential defeating factors that Devlin outlines. Accordingly, the

appointed law makers of society have the duty to balance conflicting values…and to form a judgement according to the merits of each case. (Devlin 1965: 117)

Devlin identifies a series of “factors which should restrict the use of the criminal law”, even where an immorality or moral wrong has been identified (Devlin 1965: viii). Balances must be struck as between “factors of principle” and “factors of expediency” (we examine some of these in the next section). Hence it will often be the case that the posited wrongness or immorality will not be a sufficient ground for legal coercion.

As far as Feinberg’s formulation is concerned, it is perhaps revealing to contrast his formulation of the harm principle (which we discuss below in section 4 ) with his formulation of legal moralism cited above.

Harm to others : It is always a good reason in support of penal legislation that it would be effective in preventing (eliminating, reducing) harm to persons other than the actor (the one prohibited from acting) and that there is probably no other means that is equally effective at no greater cost to other values . (Feinberg 1984: 26, emphasis added)

In formulating his harm principle, Feinberg is careful to qualify his central claim with conditions relating to what would be “effective” and of what the “cost” may be to “other values”. Not so, however, when he formulates legal moralism. This may be no more than an oversight. However, considerations of the sort—potential “effectiveness”, “cost to other values”—are central to legal moralists as will be seen in the next section (Devlin 1965; Moore 1997: 663–665). Stressing these, as regards the harm principle, but omitting them, as regards legal moralism, leaves the unfair impression that the former has a subtlety and a realism that the latter lacks. Furthermore, Feinberg’s formulation makes wrongdoing or immorality sound like something of an afterthought or a factor of only marginal importance to the criminalization question. The legal moralist by contrast sees wrongdoing or immorality not as marginal or in play only after harm and offence have had their due, but as central or pivotal. Wrongs, as Devlin would have it, “shape” crimes. Of the best known—murder, rape, battery, theft, fraud, arson—so called mala in se —we should say “a moral idea shapes the content of the law” (Devlin 1965: 27). It is true, the moralist will say, that while these crimes are shaped by morality, the criminal offence of, say, murder is not identical to the moral wrong of murder as law will import various other requirements, of legality and so on; for example the law

must trim the edges so that they present a line sharp enough for the clear acquittal or condemnation which the administration of justice requires. (Devlin 1965: 27)

The wrongdoing is, however, essential. Hence the legal moralist takes murder, fraud etc as ripe for criminalization because they are wrongful. They may (or may not) be wrongful because harmful; but from the fact that harms form a significant subset of wrongs, we should not be tempted to put the cart before the horse. Harms matter a great deal, but this is because they are often a kind of wrong. As Devlin’s fellow legal moralist Michael Moore puts it

we care about harm to non-consenting victims because to cause such harms (and sometimes, to fail to prevent them) breaches our moral obligations. (Moore 1997: 649)

If one were to revise Feinberg’s definition of legal moralism so as to be symmetrical with his definition of the harm principle one would get something closer to the essence of the position: It is (always or sometimes) a good reason in support of penal legislation that it would be effective in preventing (eliminating, reducing) wrongs and that there is probably no other means that is equally effective at no greater cost to other values. [ 3 ]

Legal moralism, then, broadly comes in two parts, first, a wrong or immorality is identified and, second, a set of countervailing factors are considered; and considered with the aim of reaching an all-things-considered-judgement on whether legal coercion should be deployed. The wrong may be strong enough to see off the countervailing factors, as the case may be, or the factors may be powerful enough to defeat the wrong, all things considered. Thus, some wrongs will be tolerable, according to this position, and some will be intolerable. Beyond this core of the position, legal moralist accounts diverge significantly. Moore takes a specific philosophy of punishment, a form of retributivism, as an essential component of his account (Moore 1997). Duff argues that only a subset of moral wrongs should be criminalizable—public, not private wrongs (Duff 2016, 2018). Tadros, whose relationship to legal moralism is complex, also excludes a subset of moral wrongs as potentially criminalizable, for example “less serious wrongs committed in families” (Tadros 2016a: 131). Against this Moore accepts there is initially reason to criminalize all kinds of morally wrongful conduct—even breach of contract or treachery among friends—and leaves it to the second part of the structure mentioned above, the countervailing factors, to block the absurdity of criminalizing such conduct (Moore 1997, 2016). There is also considerable variation between legal moralists as to how “morality” is to be understood. Notably, Devlin’s understanding of morality is widely rejected by his successors. Below the flexibility of the approach will be emphasized. We return to the question of how the “morality” in “legal moralism” is to be understood in section 3 .

2. Legal Moralism: Restrictive Factors that Can Defeat Prima Facie Wrongs

The defeating factors most heavily stressed by Devlin and Moore are privacy and liberty (Devlin 1965: 16–20; Moore 1997: 76–78). As far as privacy is concerned, consider adultery and fornication. Adultery remains a criminal offence in parts of the world including certain US states (Rhode 2016). Devlin takes the wrongfulness of adultery for granted, but nevertheless holds it inappropriate to criminalize it. Jeffrie Murphy reaches the same conclusion despite saying, along the same lines as Devlin:

It does not strike me as absurd…to suggest that the sexual revolution of the 60s, and the resulting freedom many men felt to abandon their marriages and family responsibilities for sexual and other forms of so-called self-fulfilment, generated considerable social harm—particularly for women and children. (J. Murphy 2006 [2012: 70])

From considerations like this there may be a prima facie ground to criminalize in some circumstances such moral wrongs, but the conduct—all things considered—should not be criminal in Devlin’s view or Murphy’s. The clumsy tool of legal coercion is hardly likely to help remedy any wrongs here, not to mention the undesirability of official surveillance of intimate relationships.

The privacy concerns defeat any prima facie right. A legal moralist position must attend closely to what is known about the potential effects on privacy of the criminal law. Such a view would find pertinent Lawrence Tribe’s suggestion as to what the question should be in Bowers v Hardwick —that is: not the question of what Hardwick “was doing in the privacy of his bedroom, but what the State of Georgia was doing there” (quoted in Suk 2009a: 689). [ 4 ] More recently Jeannie Suk has explored the relationship between the criminal law and the value of privacy and intimate relationships. Though not writing from any self-declared legal moralist perspective the ideas illustrate the kind of balanced exploration that the legal moralist seeks. The criminal law in many jurisdictions—Suk’s focus is largely on New York County—showed, historically, a reluctance to enter the intimate space of the home at the heavy cost of enabling domestic abuse against women. This has been replaced in many jurisdictions, such as New York County, by the criminalization in various guises of domestic abuse. An improvement to be sure. However, Suk points to some complex resulting tensions “between protecting women from intimate violence” and respecting their “self-determination” (Suk 2009a: 690). Certain criminal law techniques, such as protection orders that seek the end of an intimate relationship can amount, she claims, to “state-imposed de facto divorce” (Suk 2009a: 685; 2009b) and to various contexts in which “the particular desires of individual women” do not “control” a particular area of their intimate lives (Suk 2009a: 690). Suk’s aim is not to deny that the criminal law should be used to criminalize and enforce specific laws against domestic abuse; the wrong (and harm) of domestic abuse remains a ground for such intervention. It is rather to focus on the delicate balances implied by legal enforcement of such wrongdoing against the value of privacy, intimacy, and self-determination and to evaluate certain specific legal techniques in the light of such a focus. It has led to numerous responses (see Suk 2009a, which contains reactions from eight commentators; on domestic abuse see also Friedman 2003, Dempsey 2009).

This approach to privacy is not one accepted by all legal moralists. The usual two-part structure of legal moralism—the wrongs and the countervailing factors—was noted above. Devlin and Moore treat privacy as a potentially defeating countervailing factor, an aspect of the second part of that structure as we have just seen. Duff, however, treats it as a criterion to determine what counts as a wrong before even reaching the question of countervailing factors, in other words as an aspect of the first part of that structure. For Duff, the criminal law is, or should be, limited to the definition and declaration of public wrongs; wrongness, for him, “is a reason for criminalization—but only if it is committed within the public realm” (Duff 2018: 100). In insisting on this, Duff is departing from Devlin’s claim:

that it is not possible to set theoretical limits to the power of the State to legislate against immorality. It is not possible to settle in advance exceptions to the general rule or to define inflexibly areas of morality into which the law is in no circumstances to be allowed to enter. (Devlin 1965: 12–13)

The “private realm” for Duff—which he aspires to define in advance, albeit not “inflexibly”—is precisely an area of morality into which the (criminal) law is not to be allowed to enter.

As for liberty, “there must be”, says Devlin, “toleration of the maximum individual freedom that is consistent with the integrity of society” (Devlin 1965: 16). “Toleration” only arises in relation to conduct of which one disapproves: toleration is not approval (Devlin 1965: 18; cf. Oberdiek 2001; Green 2008). He gives two examples—cruelty to animals and –the issue with which his view is most famously associated—homosexual sex and, as he puts it, the “general abhorrence of homosexuality” in the UK in the late 1950s and early 1960s (Devlin 1965: 17). As regards both, his question is: are they beyond toleration by the criminal law? Devlin’s answer is yes to the first and—although there is a widespread erroneous view on this in the literature [ 5 ] —no to the second. In other words, liberty or freedom of human choice cannot defeat the prima facie right of society to criminalize cruelty to animals on grounds of its wrongfulness, but, in the case of consensual homosexual sex in private, it can (Devlin, Birmingham et al. 1965; cf. Devlin 1965: ix). On the latter issue, one might certainly disagree (to put it mildly) with the claim that the reason gay sex ought not to be criminalized is that it is within the bounds of toleration, for that implies that such conduct is morally wrongful in the first place. And one might also strongly doubt the plausibility of Devlin’s means of discerning where the boundary of maximum individual freedom lies—turning both on how widespread a moral belief is and on how intensely it is felt and believed. [ 6 ] We will return below to these points when we consider how “morality” should be best understood in legal moralism ( section 3 ). The point for now is to illustrate the structure of a legal moralism such as that of Devlin. In short Devlin took both animal cruelty and homosexuality to be prima facie morally wrong, but took the former all things considered to hold firm against liberty as a potential defeating condition, and the latter to be defeated by liberty (and other factors) when all things are considered. Moore in his brand of legal moralism also stresses the place of liberty. In his view, “there is always some reason not to legally coerce behaviour, namely, that to do so diminishes the opportunities of those coerced, diminishes the likelihood of autonomously chosen rightful behaviour etc.” (Moore 1997: 749; 2014).

There is a controversy here as to whether the negative liberty which Moore explicitly invokes (and which Devlin assumes) can ground the requisite prima facie reason against legal coercion (for scepticism see Tadros 2016b: 79–82 and the response in Moore 2016: 352). [ 7 ] This raises the issue much explored in the philosophical literature of the extent to which liberty should be understood as “negative liberty” or “positive liberty” or some combination of the two (Carter 2019). Negative liberty, as Ian Carter puts it,

is the absence of obstacles, barriers or constraints. One has negative liberty to the extent that actions are available to one in this negative sense. Positive liberty is the possibility of acting—or the fact of acting—in such a way as to take control of one’s life and realize one’s fundamental purposes. (Carter 2019)

Amy Baehr blocks out how the negative/positive liberty distinction takes shape in liberal feminist writing, labelling approaches of the former kind “classical-liberal feminism”, and approaches of the latter kind as “egalitarian-liberal feminism” (Baehr 2021). As we saw in the previous subsection in relation to privacy, it is a sign of the potential flexibility of a broad legal moralist approach, that liberal-feminist accounts of freedom could potentially be deployed so as to yield potential defeating conditions for all-things-considered determinations in given cases of whether legal coercion can legitimately be deployed to counter an identified wrong. We touch on this issue again below ( section 6.2 ).

The legal moralist notion of defeaters—the conditions that can potentially defeat a prima facie reason to impose legal coercion on the basis of moral wrongdoing—should not be thought of as closed, but rather as flexible and subject to evolution or change. The notion fits comfortably with an established set of considerations that have been developed since the 1960s, based on the “crime tariff” and other mechanisms at work in the criminal law (Packer 1964, 1968; Moore 1997: 664). The idea of the crime tariff is that certain kinds of (perceived) wrongful behaviour will be engaged in, one way or another, whether it is criminal or not. That, of course, is not a conclusive objection to criminalization. If it were, the criminalization of murder or theft would be ruled out. However, if one looks at the predictable effects of criminalization of given wrongful conduct, it may make matters still worse than staying the hand of the criminal law. For one effect of criminalization is that the price of products (for example dangerous drugs) or services (for example sex work) will go up and will attract suppliers willing to break the law systematically and introduce a plethora of criminal gangs into societies, among other effects. The result may be worse than leaving well (or quite bad) alone. Michael Moore, for example, writes:

Prostitution… does not go away by being legislated against, as the experience of all societies has shown. By making it criminal, however, the supply is artificially restricted to those willing to engage in criminal behaviour, so that prices and profits are such as to draw in organized criminal activity. (Moore 1997: 664; cf. Flanigan & Watson 2020).

Devlin appeared to be anticipating this argument when pointing out a factor that needed to be weighed in considering whether abortion (which he appeared to assume was morally wrongful) should be, or should remain, criminal. Abortions, in certain circumstances, will be sought irrespective of whether the conduct is criminal. But, if criminal, they will be performed by amateur, unskilled “backstreet” practitioners, operating outside of legal regulation. This renders the procedure dangerous in a way it would not be if properly attested professionals were undertaking the procedure; and punishment may seem appropriate for anyone causing or risking such danger. However, the dangerousness of this conduct, said Devlin, is “largely” based on the facts that “it is illegal and therefore performed only by the unskilled” (Devlin 1965: 24). This again yields a factor of potential relevance—even to those who, like Devlin, believe abortion to be morally wrong. Whatever the conclusion, such a consideration is a factor to be weighed in the balance.

There has been much research in the intervening decades on how norm-subjects will respond to any potential use of the criminal law. Will they endorse it, ignore it, seek to undermine it? All of this can make a difference to the wisdom of criminalizing in the first place. Tom Tyler has argued that to a large extent obedience to the law is based on what is perceived by people to be legitimate and to be respected. The extent to which people obey because threatened by legal sanctions is, by contrast, exaggerated (Tyler 2006). Paul Robinson stresses the need for laws to be made that do not stray too far from the norms already accepted by the people. For if they do, the people will not stigmatize the conduct, which may blunt or compromise the effectiveness of the norms in question (Robinson 2000). Similarly, legal officials may find various ways of underenforcing norms if they stray too far from those generally accepted, again blunting their efficacy. Bill Stuntz points to the phenomenon of “self-defeating crimes” (Stuntz 2000). A series of factors of the sort have most recently been examined by Jacob Barrett and Gerald Gaus (Barrett & Gaus 2020). The idea of potential defeating conditions is a highly flexible one, not a once-for-all set of conditions with any rigidity; the list will inevitably change and develop. A further issue of potential relevance to the question of what conduct should be criminalized (and how) focusses on the consequences of applying the criminal law in given areas. There is, for example, a differential impact of the criminal law on some races in many jurisdictions (Yankah 2019). One might add to a list of potential defeaters the problem that enforcement of a given proposed or current offence is not possible under current conditions in any tolerably fair way. In the United Kingdom, for example, the politician David Lammy has written a report on racial disparities across the criminal justice system and proposed a principle for government of “explain or reform”: if governments cannot provide an evidence-based explanation for apparent disparities, then reforms should be introduced to address them (Lammy 2017).

The above discussion emphasized the legal moralist’s defeating factors because of their importance to the position and because, as we have seen, legal moralism is sometimes misleadingly characterized without reference to them. It was also noted that Feinberg holds such factors to be of crucial importance to the version of the harm principle he endorses. Such factors will surely be largely ecumenical as between the rival approaches.

As we have seen, Devlin took homosexuality and animal cruelty to be morally wrongful and therefore his reason for supporting the decriminalization of the first and the continued criminalization of the second was that they, respectively, ought to be tolerated and ought not to be tolerated (see footnote 5). Notably neither Devlin nor Hart addressed the question of why—in virtue of what—can it be asserted or denied that homosexuality is morally wrongful. For Devlin that is hardly to the point, for “what the law maker has to ascertain is not the true belief but the common belief”(Devlin 1965: 94). By contrast Devlin’s fellow legal moralist, Moore, would take Devlin’s support for decriminalization of homosexual sex to be the right result for the wrong reason; homosexuality, not being in any way morally wrong, should not be criminalized for that straightforward reason; the question of toleration should never arise (Moore 1997: 756; Corvino 2013; Pickett 2020).

Devlin’s account is a moral relativist one. He relativizes what is morally good to the beliefs of a given society (where “deeply felt and not manufactured”; Devlin 1965: 17). The attraction for Devlin of moral relativism was his belief that it would yield a morality generally of the society subject to it, without conceding “moral expertise” to any (elite) group of persons. He seemed to assimilate the “rationalist morality” he rejected to the views of an educated elite (Devlin 1965: 91–92). [ 8 ] Since Hart’s critique, few have found the relativist aspect of Devlin’s account convincing (Hart 1963 [1982: 17–24]). Devlin’s view appears to exemplify what Bernard Williams styled as “vulgar and unregenerate” relativism (B. Williams 1972: 34, cf. Fricker 2013). Such relativism—as Williams paints it—is composed of three propositions:

1. “right” means … “right for a given society” [also presumably by the same token: “wrong” means “wrong for a given society”]; 2. right[/wrong] “for a given society” is to be understood in the functionalist sense’ [i.e., for the persistence of that society]; and that 3. (therefore) it is wrong for people in one society to condemn, interfere with, etc., the values of another society.   (B. Williams 1972: 34–39, numbering added; cf. the distinction between “positive morality” and “critical morality” in Hart 1963 [1982: 17–24])

As noted above, Devlin affirmed the first of William’s propositions. In industrialized societies, Devlin tells us, it is generally true that monogamy “is built into the house in which we live and could not be removed without bringing it down” (Devlin 1965: 10). But this is merely a contingent truth and if our houses were built differently—around polygamy—the content of the law to be enforced could legitimately be the opposite of what it is (Devlin 1965: 114). As for the second, it is equally clear that Devlin understood wrongness “for a given society” in “the functional sense” of what threatened the persistence of that society. A society is constituted by its “common morality” or “moral structure” or “public morality” and its morality is as necessary to it as “a recognised government”, If a society’s morality is not sufficiently enforced the society will “disintegrate”; and the society accordingly has a right to defend itself against attacks on that morality (Devlin 1965: 10).

Devlin’s “disintegration argument” appears fatally wounded by Hart’s initial criticism of it. As Hart puts it, Devlin moves

from the acceptable proposition that some shared morality is essential to the existence of any society to the unacceptable proposition that a society is identical with its morality as that is at any given moment of its history, so that a change in its morality is tantamount to a destruction of society. (Hart 1963 [1982: 51])

The former claim is plausible if restricted to what Hobbes and Hume characterized as the moral minimum essential for social life:

rules restraining the free use of violence and minimal forms of rules regarding honesty, promise-keeping, fair dealing, and property. (Hart 1967 [1983: 258])

If these ceased to be enforced, it is likely that a different and more dangerous state-of-affairs would ensue; one might well say the original society had disintegrated. Hart can afford to concede this. Such a Hobbesian-Humean minimum is accounted for by the harm principle Devlin rejects. Devlin’s argument, however, needs the disintegration thesis to apply more widely, potentially to every crime of a community, be that to homosexuality, animal cruelty, bigamy, incest etc (to “every jot and tittle” as Hart puts it: Hart 1967 [1983: 258]). These need to be protected on pain of the disintegration of society. Since Devlin gives no empirical evidence linking the destruction of past societies with the non-enforcement of their rules, this appears not to be an empirical claim. [ 9 ] But as a conceptual argument it is highly dubious. For as Hart says

Taken strictly, it would prevent us saying that the morality of a given society has changed, and would compel us instead to say that one society had disappeared and another one taken its place (Hart 1963 [1982: 51–52])

Only a claim of this strength seems able to support Devlin’s belief that any deviation from a society’s shared morality is an existential threat to it.

A different objection is this: to assimilate right and wrong with the question of a society’s survival assumes that the survival of a specific society is necessarily good. It may be true that if certain steps are not taken, the society will disintegrate. Apartheid in South Africa disintegrated. What if by a more sustained enforcement of its central racist elements it had managed to persist longer? Would this continued existence be underwritten by a moral right? Does anyone now owe the society the duty to restore the system or did such a duty lie for a period after its disintegration? The suggestions are absurd. The point of course is that some societies are so lacking in legitimacy that it may be for the best that they disintegrate and are replaced. Devlin goes too far when he says “What is important is not the quality of the creed but the strength of the belief in it” (Devlin 1965: 114). While his concern was the use of legal coercion within a specific society rather than with criticism of other societies, Devlin also appeared to hold to the third of Williams’ propositions above in seeking to exclude standards external to the beliefs of the society. Legal moralism, then, surely needs foundations other than those Devlin sought to provide.

This impression is buttressed by another concern about his account. For what is the status and basis of liberty and privacy, for example, in Devlin’s account? As we have seen he took them to be powerful enough to override certain immoralities in determining what should be criminalized. But what if the ordinary jury member or person on the Clapham omnibus just does not care that much about privacy or liberty? What if, say, they take the view that adultery should be criminalized never mind the very high cost to privacy? Should privacy and liberty be simply downgraded as a result? There is no indication that Devlin would accept such a conclusion or even that the possibility occurred to him. Similarly, Devlin took it that the law should be “perfectly impartial in matters of religion” and this seems in no way sensitive to whether or not the ordinary member of society endorses such impartiality (Devlin 1965: 62). He appears to take liberty and privacy and other defeaters as safeguards applicable independently of whether ordinary people would accept their validity. In this he appears to have been simply inconsistent.

What alternative foundations could legal moralism have if Devlin’s brand of moral relativism is to be rejected? In the light of Devlin’s stress on wrongdoing as a prima facie ground for legal coercion, one possibility might be an ethics of prima facie duty associated with W.D Ross (Ross 1930; Skelton 2012). And of course, any of the other numerous theories of what makes wrong action wrong—consequentialist, Kantian, natural law, rights-based, virtue ethics—could potentially form such a foundation (Timmons 2013). [ 10 ] Michael Moore combines his legal moralism with a strong version of metaphysical realism (Moore 1997). Presumably, however, such strong metaethical commitments can be bracketed for the more specific questions raised by legal moralism. Jeremy Waldron for example suggests that an anti-realist or quasi-realist view, positing moral truth, albeit based ultimately on subjective sources “inside our own attitudes, desires, and natures”, could serve as well as an out-and-out realist view of Moore’s variety (Waldron 1999: 171). Again, while a legal moralist must surely reject a “vulgar” relativist view of Devlin’s stripe, it may not follow that a more sophisticated moral relativist grounding for legal moralism could not be attempted (Wong 2006; Rovane 2013; Velleman 2015; cf. Fricker 2013). Indeed Duff’s legal moralism is alleged by others to contain moral relativist commitments, a claim he himself rejects (Moore 2014: 199; Tadros 2016a: 121–128; Duff 2018: 232)

Far and away the best-known proposal for a principled limit to the law is the “harm principle” from John Stuart Mill’s On Liberty. The pivotal sentence of its most famous passage reads:

the only purpose for which power can rightfully be exercised over any member of a civilised community against his will is to prevent harm to others. (Mill On Liberty , Ch. 1, para 9)

Harm to others , can be contrasted with moral wrongfulness or immorality—the legal moralist’s starting point; with offence to others; and with harm to persons choosing to engage in, or consenting to, the relevant conduct (anti-paternalism). At least as far as Mill’s canonical statement is concerned, moralism, offence and paternalism are ruled out as legitimate bases for legal coercion. The State may legitimately stop A from beating up B, thereby limiting his freedom of action, because this prevents harm to B. And it may stop A from stealing from B for the same reason. But the State oversteps its proper limits on this view if it purports to stop A smashing up his own property; or to protect C from the distaste she will feel knowing that A is doing this. And it may not treat the wrongfulness of conduct, in the absence of any unconsented-to harm, as a basis for legal coercion: it may not for example prevent “bloody gladiatorial contests presented by voluntary performers before consenting audiences” (Feinberg 1984: 13). For the harm principle, says Mill, is “entitled to govern absolutely the dealing of society with the individual in the way of compulsion and control” (Mill On Liberty , Ch. 1, para 9)

In his four-volume work, the Moral Limits of the Criminal Law Joel Feinberg sets out to defend a version of the harm principle that he takes to be firmly in the spirit of Mill (Feinberg 1984, 1985, 1986, 1990).

The Liberal Position : The harm and offense principles, duly clarified and qualified, between them exhaust the class of good reasons for criminal prohibitions.

This is compounded, first, of Feinberg’s “harm to others” principle stating, as we saw in section 1 :

Harm to others : It is always a good reason in support of penal legislation that it would be effective in preventing (eliminating, reducing) harm to persons other than the actor (the one prohibited from acting) and that there is probably no other means that is equally effective at no greater cost to other values. (Feinberg 1984: 26)

But Feinberg goes beyond Mill’s officially stated position in adding, secondly, the offense principle:

Offense to others : It is always a good reason in support of a proposed criminal prohibition that it is probably necessary to prevent serious offense to persons other than the actor and would probably be an effective means to that end if enacted. (Feinberg 1984: 26)

Though this “offense to others principle” goes beyond Mill’s canonical position, Feinberg believed there to be support in Mill’s writings for the addition of offense as a ground and in any case argued that there are independent grounds for thinking the addition of the offense principle strengthens the Millian position. The place of offense and relatedly “moral distress” remains controversial and has inspired an extensive literature (Feinberg 1985; Hart 1963 [1982: 46]; Waldron 1987 [1993]; Simester & von Hirsch 2011: 99–140; Edwards 2019)

There is an important qualification to be made to Feinberg’s “harm to others” principle. One reason why one might want to treat harm as special is the yearning for a concept for practical use that is “simple, determinate” and “purely empirical” (Feinberg 1984: 214). Such a determinate empirical concept, if it exists, could function free of the controversies that usually attend normative concepts. Everyone, from vastly diverse cultures, philosophies and opinions could get behind it, without fear of compromising what they hold dear. It is clear, however, that Feinberg abandons any hope, if this ever was a feasible ambition, of blocking out any such purely empirical notion. Instead he builds into his harm principle a strong element of moral wrongfulness. As we have observed, his harm principle is designed to reject moral wrongfulness as a legitimating ground for legal coercion, but the crucial qualification here is that it rejects wrongfulness without more as a legitimate basis for legal coercion. Moral wrongs, however, remain highly significant to the account. For harms “produced by justified or excused conduct (‘harms that are not wrongs’)” are said by him not to count as “harms” for the sake of his harm principle. It is thus not any harm to others that constitutes a good reason in support of legal coercion. It is the harms that are produced by “morally indefensible conduct” that matter (Feinberg 1984: 215). In other words, the proponent of Feinberg’s harm principle must be highly concerned with moral wrongs and immorality, perhaps almost as concerned as the legal moralist.

On the one hand, this allows Feinberg to deal satisfyingly with a raft of potential counterexamples. Since, for him, a good reason for coercion will present itself only if the harm in question is wrongful, he can avoid designating as harmful setbacks to persons of the order of losing a professional tennis competition or of being driven out of business by a rival’s superior product, even if the consequences feel like, and are, terrible events in the lives of the individuals concerned. Be they so terrible they are not harms in the relevant sense for Feinberg, as they do not spring from any wrongdoing. On the other hand, the necessity of a moral wrong in his account of harms opens him up to potential criticism. For example, it might be claimed that it is the wrongs that are doing the essential explanatory work, while harm is a redundant or near-redundant addition. Or the strong moral wrongness element in the account might be taken as a tacit admission that the reason the relevant harms matter in the first place is that they are morally wrongful; and if that point goes through, the next question may be: why, then do wrongs that are not harms not also matter enough to form, on occasion (and subject to potential defeating conditions), a valid reason for legal coercion?

Feinberg, however, is clearly Millian in his rejection of paternalism.

Paternalism : It is always a good reason in support of a prohibition that it is probably necessary to prevent harm (physical, psychological, or economic) to the actor himself and that there is probably no other means that is equally effective at no greater cost to other values. (Feinberg 1984: 26–27; Feinberg 1986)

His strong anti-paternalism is not equally hostile to everything that might be described as legal paternalism. He distinguishes “soft paternalism” from “hard paternalism”. In many cases the forcible implementation of a person’s will can accord with his personal autonomy. Feinberg describes such cases as involving “soft paternalism” and contrasts them with those involving “hard paternalism” (Feinberg 1986: 26). It is the “hard” variety that Feinberg sets himself against, the forcible coercion of a person against her will for her own good. This he rules out on grounds of legitimacy. In fact, he does not believe that “soft” paternalism is really paternalism at all properly so-called and so stops short of adding it to his list of potentially legitimating reasons for legal coercion (G. Dworkin 2020).

Whether or not Feinberg broke significantly with Mill on the question of offense, a much larger break with Mill is evident in the respective defences of the harm principle offered by H.L.A Hart and Joseph Raz. Speaking of Hart, Devlin observed that he “mutinied” against Mill and “ran paternalism up the mast” (Devlin 1965: 132). Hart indeed accuses Mill of carrying “his protests against paternalism to lengths that may now appear to us fantastic” (Hart 1963 [1982: 32]). Furthermore, anticipating parts of the “Nudge” movement that emerged fully this century (Sunstein 2014), Hart speaks of

a general decline in the belief that individuals know their own interests best, and to an increased awareness that a great range of factors which diminish the significance to be attached to an apparently free choice or consent. (Hart 1963 [1982: 32–33])

Raz in turn speaks of his “ready embrace of various paternalistic measures”, asserting it is “senseless to formulate either a general pro- or a general anti-paternalistic conclusion” (Raz 1986: 422: Simester & von Hirsch 2011: Part IV; Stanton-Ife 2020: 211–220). The issue of paternalism is of considerable importance to the limits of the law, but for a deeper discussion beyond the brief remarks just made see the entry on paternalism (G. Dworkin 2020; cf. Hurd 2018; De Marneffe 2018; Conly 2018).

Hence Hart and Raz defend a “harm principle”, not a “harm to others” principle. Both nevertheless argue that it will often be the case that the state should not act paternalistically, only not in such a way that an exclusionary principle is merited. The dramatic differences between major proponents of the harm principle makes it misleading to speak of the harm principle as one principle, although one suspects the term is too far embedded in the debate to be dislodged. Therefore we continue to speak of the harm principle, though strictly speaking, there is more than one. The table below illustrates the divergence in the views of the leading thinkers associated with the harm principle. No one of them has an account with conclusions identical to any of the others (see also Edwards 2014). What unites them all is the rejection of legal moralism.

A family of harm-principle accounts:
potentially legitimating grounds for legal coercion
Legitimate basis for coercion? Harm to Others? Offence to Others? Harm to Self? Legal Moralism?
Mill Yes No No No
Feinberg Yes Yes No No
Hart Yes Yes, can be Yes, can be No
Raz Yes No ] Yes, can be No

5. What is Harm?

Proponents of the harm principle often proceed without supplying any definition or understanding of “harm”. Mill himself gives no explicit general definition of what he means by the word, satisfying himself with various examples, contextual stipulations and hints:

he seems throughout to think no further explanation is necessary, and to count on any literate speaker of English to accept his application of the word or of some proxy for it. (Brown 2017: 411)

As we will see, other writers consider they can detect in Mill one or more ways to define or understand the term. Perhaps, as well as relying on general linguistic intuitions, one can simply cite paradigm cases. These come easily to mind; harm as “broken bones and stolen purses” as Joel Feinberg puts it (Feinberg 1984: 214). Certainly, one harms others, on any folk understanding of the term, by killing, raping, beating, defrauding, or stealing. But the ordinary sense of harm may also suggest that a transitory pain is a harm and may also have rather porous borders with other normative concepts such as “wrong”, May there, then, be trouble ahead developing a sufficiently determinate, discriminating, and workable conception of harm for purposes of applying the harm principle?

Various definitions and understandings of “harm” have been offered. One derived from Mill takes harmful conduct to be “other-concerning” or “other-regarding conduct” and, conversely, harmless conduct is “self-regarding” (Mill On Liberty , ch. 1, para 9). Accordingly, if some actions have no social consequences, they affect only the actor and are therefore harmless. Hart seems discomforted enough by “critics” of this Millian suggestion to have been unwilling to adopt it himself across the board. He surely had James Fitzjames Stephen’s critique of Mill in mind among others (Stephen 1873 [1993]). These critics, he says,

have urged that the line which Mill attempts to draw between actions with which the law may interfere and those with which it may not is illusory. “No man is an island”; and in an organised society it is impossible to identify classes of actions which harm no one or no one but the individual who does them. (Hart 1963 [1982: 5])

Despite seeming to take Stephen’s point against Mill, however, Hart goes on to adopt the other-regarding/self-regarding understanding in a limited context: so far, he says, as the “special topic of sexual morality” is concerned there may exist a realm or area of conduct that is harmless; here it does seem, “prima facie plausible that there are actions immoral by accepted standards and yet not harmful to others” (Hart 1963 [1982: 5]). It is not, however, clear how this understanding of harm is to be reconciled with Hart’s other uses of the term. For example, he discusses (sceptically) whether the “moral distress” of persons occasioned by the moral wrongdoing of others should count as harm to them (Hart 1963 [1982: 46]); cf. Waldron 1987 [1993]); and he asserts that animal cruelty should be criminal, not pace Devlin to “enforce a moral principle”, but on account of animal suffering. If there is a coherent way of bringing these various understandings of harm together, Hart does not himself supply it.

Another understanding of “harm” again takes its cue from Mill, this time from his many references to the “interests” of persons—for example: “insofar as these concern the interests of no person but himself” and “such actions as are prejudicial to the interests of others” (Mill On Liberty , ch. 5, para 2). The important distinction is not that which regards others versus that which regards oneself. It is that which is in the interests of others versus that which is in the interests of oneself. The seminal essay for this reading is from 1960 by John Rees (Rees 1960; cf. Saunders 2016), though Hart appears not to have been aware of it. Rees paved the way for Feinberg’s development of harm as “the setback of interests”. Hence, in addition to Feinberg’s addition of wrongfulness commented on above, Feinberg’s defines harm as “those states of set-back interest that are the consequence of wrongful acts or omissions by others” (Feinberg 1984: 215).

This Mill-inspired move of Rees and Feinberg, of defining harm in terms of interests, smacks of defining one unclear concept in terms of another unclear concept (Miller 2010: 119). The question of what is in a person’s interests—what is at stake for her—is itself a question that requires considerable elucidation. In Derek Parfit’s terms should we understand “interests” in “desire-fulfilment” terms, in “hedonistic” terms, or in accordance with an “objective list” which holds

certain things are good or bad for people, whether or not the people would want to have the good things, or to avoid the bad things? (Parfit 1984: 499)

Might one reasonably think that adjudicating the conflict between hedonistic, desire-fulfilment and objective list understandings of interests is an undertaking no less complex than the harm principle/legal moralism conflict itself? Take an “objective list” understanding of a person’s interests. According to Parfit this might include—as good for a person—“moral goodness, rational activity, the development of one’s abilities” and so on; and it might include—as bad for a person—being “deprived of dignity” (Parfit 1984: 499). If this is always or sometimes the best account of interests, the whole question of “moral harm” that the harm principle aims to expel is potentially reintroduced. The question of which account, or combination of accounts, is the most compelling is very much a live issue (Fletcher 2016).

Another influential understanding of “harm” is that initially proposed by Raz: “To harm a person is to diminish his prospects, to affect adversely his possibilities” (Raz 1986: 414; Gardner & Shute 2000; Simester & von Hirsch 2011; Edwards 2014, 2019). Harm is essentially understood not as a setback to interests, but a setback to autonomy. Autonomy is essentially understood as the ability to choose between an adequate range of valuable options, while in possession of the appropriate capacities to make such choices and while sufficiently independent of others. There are plainly numerous ways one can set back such autonomy. The problem of explaining why pain is harmful raises its head again. Many would take the infliction of pain on another to be harmful, without waiting to ask if the victim has suffered any setback in her ability to choose between an adequate range of valuable options, which surely, she will often not have done. And what of Devlin’s case of harm to animals? Devlin is likely to pop up at this point to repeat his view that the reason we criminalize cruelty to animals is that it is morally wrong and no potential defeating factor is strong enough to overturn that judgement for purposes of criminalization. There is no need to establish any harm in the first place. Hart, as touched on above, while accepting harm must be part of the story, offered the avoidance of “suffering” as the ground for criminalizing animal cruelty. Setback to autonomy or prospect-harm, however, looks like a non-starter, for animals, though beings that can be harmed, are not autonomous beings, at least on any standard account. Similarly, severely mentally disordered persons may in some cases lack the capacity for autonomy, but it is plain as day that they can be harmed, something the “setback to autonomy” or “prospect harm” conception seems ill equipped to account for (Stanton-Ife 2010: 157–162; Tadros 2011).

One upshot of the varying, sometimes implicit, understanding of harm is surely that anyone propounding an argument based on the harm principle needs to be clear about how they are using the term “harm”. For the term may hide a host of questions that themselves need to be resolved.

6. Foundations of the Harm Principle

Moving on from questions of definition, what are the foundations of the harm principle? Mill, together with Jeremy Bentham and Henry Sidgwick, was one of three giants of nineteenth century utilitarianism. He declared utility to be the ultimate appeal on all ethical questions. Speaking of his harm principle, he also declared:

I forego any advantage which could be derived to my argument from the idea of abstract right, as a thing independent from utility. (Mill On Liberty , ch. 1.11 [1993: 79])

The harm principle sounds rather like the (foregone) stuff of abstract right, so how is utility to give any support to the harm principle? At first sight, the principle of utility looks like a straightforward rival to the harm principle, not its sturdy foundation. Mill held of the principle of utility that

actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. (Mill Utilitarianism , ch. 2.2 [1993: 7]

This last formulation seems to counsel states to keep their options open in their law-making. “Do what you can to reverse unhappiness”, the advice seems to be, “and do what you can to promote happiness”,

Coerce to prevent harm to others if that will reverse unhappiness; coerce for some other end if that will equally do the trick.

But as we have just seen, coercion to prevent harmless wrongdoing is ruled out by Mill, irrespective of whether such an action is the state’s best bet for reversing unhappiness.

The path to reconciling the harm principle with utilitarianism is often thought to be some form of indirect utilitarianism (Gray 1996; Mulgan 2007: 117–119). The distinction is drawn between a criterion of rightness and a decision procedure (Mulgan 2007: 117–119). Thus, on this indirect view the words “actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness” is not any part of a decision procedure; it is a criterion of rightness. Sometimes, perhaps often, a criterion of rightness will itself feature heavily in a decision procedure. But at other times a decision procedure will not contain the supreme criterion of rightness. Acting always to promote happiness or minimize unhappiness may be self-defeating for various reasons or impossible in the practical circumstances of ignorance that ordinary people face. Over the course of a lifetime and across all the activities of a legal system, more utility will be produced and disutility avoided if the harm principle has the place Mill argues it has, despite the fact that this will repeatedly require the sacrifice of some utility in day to day legal dealings. Much of this, for Mill, relates to the importance of human liberty to happiness (Gray 1996: 136). Demonstrating that one can really derive something as strong as the harm principle (“to govern absolutely”) in this way is a formidable challenge. It is subject, among other things, to scepticism about the workability of the distinction between criterion of rightness and decision procedure (Griffin 1994; Mulgan 2007). John Gray’s book-long attempt to spell out how the harm principle can be underpinned by indirect utilitarianism came to be repudiated by Gray himself (Gray 1996: postscript) . Contemporary consequentialism, however, continues to flourish (Sinnott-Armstrong 2019); and many accounts of the harm principle still see a form of utilitarianism as the best grounding for the harm principle (Sumner 2004, 2011). Moreover, there are non-utilitarian writers making related arguments in support of the harm principle. Les Green for example argues that

There can be reasons to promulgate, and attempt to conform to, an absolute norm even if the reasons that justify having a norm in that field are defeasible. (Green 2013: 191 )

Other accounts of criminalization maintain utilitarianism or a broad consequentialism but conclude the harm principle must be rejected (Petersen 2020a,b).

In recent years, value-pluralist perfectionism has been more influential than utilitarianism as a foundation for the harm principle, whether argued for explicitly or assumed (Raz 1986; Gardner & Shute 2000; Simester & Von Hirsch 2011; Edwards 2014, 2018 [2021]). Joseph Raz’s classic work The Morality of Freedom contains a defence of the harm principle (Raz 1986; cf. Raz 1989—other leading accounts of perfectionism include Hurka 1993 and Sher 1997). Raz claims that

the autonomy-based principle of freedom is best regarded as providing the moral foundation for the harm principle. (Raz 1986: 400)

At first sight this may be surprising, given the openness of perfectionists to moral reasons in general, an openness that might suggest legal moralism is its natural home so far as the limits of law are concerned. Raz asserts that there is “no fundamental principled inhibition on governments acting for any moral reason” (Raz 1989: 1230, emphasis added). Even reasons that are not “neutral”, or not “public” or some such are not in principle excluded by perfectionism (cf. G. Dworkin 2007). Again: “It makes no sense to say of a state of affairs that it is good, but that fact is no reason to do anything about it” (Raz 1989: 1230). By the same token, presumably, one could substitute the word “bad” for “good” in the previous sentence and the proposition would remain accurate. Thus our starting point is that the law should have available to it any moral reason and has the function to promote the quality of life, including the moral quality of life, of those whose lives and actions the government can affect (Raz 1986: 415). This aspect of perfectionism is apt to make some fear the oppressive imposition of styles of life on unwilling individuals (Sher 1997: 106).

However, such alarmism cannot fairly be applied to a perfectionist view such as Raz’s. It is not that anything one might describe, rightly or wrongly, as a moral reason will do. Raz’s concern is limited to states with “autonomy-respecting cultures” and with what it is to live a good life in such societies. The key, as the phrase “autonomy-respecting culture” would suggest, is autonomy. It is a state’s primary duty in the relevant kind of society to promote, protect and foster the autonomy of all citizens . This requires—on Raz’s account—furnishing all with, or preserving for all, an “adequate range of valuable options”. It also requires seeing to it that persons have the appropriate mental and other capacities to be genuine choosers in conditions of freedom and independence (Raz 1986: 372–373).

Given, then, that Raz’s starting point is that there is no principled inhibition to the law deploying any valid moral reason, an account is plainly needed of how that can be reconciled with his support for the harm principle, a large part of the point of which is to rule out certain moral reasons. But before coming to that, it will be helpful to dwell on autonomy a little longer. In section 2.2 above, the familiar distinction between two kinds of liberty, negative and positive, and a similar distinction within liberal feminist writing, were noted. Autonomy-based accounts plainly go beyond negative liberty as the absence of obstacles, barriers or constraints, and embrace the notions of positive liberty, in terms of authorship (or part-authorship) of one’s own life, ability to choose between options, realize purposes within bounds as the case may be. Furthermore, autonomy is often contrasted with heteronomy. As Marilyn Friedman puts it,

heteronomy…involves behaving or living in accord with what is in some important sense not , or other than , one’s own. (Friedman 2005: 155, author’s emphasis)

There are at least two senses, as she continues, of heteronomy, one whose sources “arise within the self, considered in abstract social isolation;” the other whose sources “derive from interpersonal relations and the treatment of a self by others” (Friedman 2005: 155). The first sense is of course important. It relates, for one thing, to the very real problems that can emerge when an agent’s “desires, emotions, passions, inclinations, drives” are not in good order, or where the agent is addicted or in the grip or a compulsion (Friedman 2005: 155). However, for all its importance, Friedman argues that heteronomy in this sense has been the “almost exclusive” focus in mainstream philosophy. The sorts of heteronomy that are by contrast based on interpersonal relations and the way some agents are treated by others, has been largely neglected outside of liberal feminist circles, where “relational autonomy” has received considerable attention (Friedman 2005: 171; cf. Mackenzie & Stoljar 2000; Friedman 2003; Stoljar 2018). This has led to the underplaying of such phenomena of considerable importance to autonomy as male dominance. Interestingly, Friedman explicitly cites Raz’s account of autonomy as a rare exception to the neglect by the mainstream of the social or interpersonal aspects of autonomy ((Friedman 2005: 171).

Thus the criticism sometimes levelled at perfectionist accounts of the good life, government or law, that they imply the oppressive imposition of styles of life, looks unlikely to get much traction on a form of liberal perfectionism, such as Raz’s, with autonomy for all so embedded in it. This, however, does not explain how an account such as Raz’s can explain its adoption of an anti-moralist harm principle in tandem with its in-principle openness to all valid moral reasons. In other words, how can one derive an anti-moralist harm principle from a position that takes any valid moral ground as in principle available to the state and the law?

Raz’s answer focusses on the coercive means at the law’s disposal:

  • There are no principled limits to the pursuit of moral goals by the law or the enhancement of the well-being of individuals on the part of the law.
  • There are (nevertheless) limits to the means that can legitimately be adopted in promoting the well-being of people and in the pursuit of moral ideals (Raz 1986: 420; George 1993: 161–188).

His autonomy principle “permits and even requires governments to create morally valuable opportunities, and to eliminate repugnant ones ” (Raz 1986: 417). It must, however, respect the harm principle in doing this. It must not use coercion to eliminate repugnant, wrongful opportunities if they are not also harmful in the relevant sense. Coercive interference is a special threat to autonomy. It often violates autonomy in two ways:

First it violates the condition of independence and expresses a relation of domination and an attitude of disrespect for the coerced individual. Second, coercion by criminal penalties is a global and indiscriminate invasion of autonomy. (Raz 1986: 418)

Let us consider both points, beginning with the second. In what sense is the use of coercion a “global and indiscriminate invasion of autonomy”? There is no doubt that sometimes it is. “Depriving a person of opportunities or of the ability to use them is”, as Raz says, “a way of causing him harm”. Again “frustrating [a person’s] pursuit of projects and relationships he has set upon” can cause harm (Raz 1986: 413). Raz alludes to the most common context for the invocation of the harm principle, namely the criminal law. Much behaviour that is criminalized is done under the threat of imprisonment and imprisonment can cut off a very large range of options; or it can reduce them considerably by various forms of disruption or destruction: of family life, deep personal relations, work opportunities, pursuit of valuable outdoor activities, political participation and so on. Richard Lippke distinguishes between the material and the symbolic dimensions of imprisonment. The symbolic dimensions relate to what message the fact of imprisonment conveys to the public and to the prisoner. The material dimensions break down into

  • restrictions on freedom of movement,
  • low levels of comfort and amenity
  • idleness, especially a paucity of opportunities for labour,
  • relative isolation from family members, friends, and the larger community,
  • significant diminution of autonomy especially insofar as prisons subject their inhabitants to a degree of bureaucratic control which might be categorised as the “subservience of youth” and
  • diminishment of privacy (Lippke 2008: 408; cf. Lippke 2007).

Though only one of Lippke’s six material dimensions explicitly mentions autonomy, all have some significant effect on it. Moreover, a similar point applies to the compulsory detention in certain circumstances of mentally disordered persons under the civil law. All of Lippke’s material dimensions can be present there too; and, while the symbolic dimensions of a criminal conviction and punishment are absent, the often-attendant stigma can compromise the autonomy of the detained mentally disordered person in question still further (Stanton-Ife 2012).

Raz, then, is right that coercion by criminal penalties can be “a global and indiscriminate invasion of autonomy”, However, there seem to be two problems with this as a basis for reconciling perfectionism and the harm principle. First, the scope of the justification seems significantly limited; while the criminal penalties can have such an effect, they often will not. For there are many more forms of criminal law coercion in regular use than imprisonment: fines, community service orders and electronic tagging orders are three examples. These methods short of imprisonment can affect options, without necessarily leaving the convicted criminal short of an adequate range of valuable options—in Raz’s terminology; the assault on autonomy will not in most be total or near-total. Take the last-mentioned example: the mandatory wearing of electronic tagging devices. There have been several high-profile cases of sports stars and other celebrities being required to wear such devices. An early example is the English soccer player, Jermaine Pennant. He broke into the first team of a top professional team—the stuff that most English lads’ dreams are made of!—but, soon after, was convicted of a drunk-driving offence. His sentence required him to wear an electronic tag but allowed him to play in top division games with his tag under his sock. [ 12 ] Despite the cloud he was under he certainly did not appear to have an inadequate range of valuable options. The argument at best seems to support the deployment of the harm principle only where lengthy periods of incarceration are deployed or threatened.

Raz does acknowledge that “other forms of coercion may be less severe”. However, he adds that

they all invade autonomy, and they all, at least in this world, do it in a fairly indiscriminate way. That is, there is no practical way of ensuring that the coercion will restrict the victims’ choice of repugnant options but will not interfere with their other choices. (Raz 1986: 418–419)

Leaving the criminal law to one side, there are other legal contexts where Raz intends the harm principle to apply where this argument appears overstated. Consider tax. Of the operation of the harm principle in relation to taxation, Raz writes:

the measures I [support] avoid direct coercion for perfectionist causes. The coercion that they involve can be fully justified on the grounds of protecting and promoting individual autonomy. The simplest example is that of taxation. Taxation is coercive. It is justified in my view only inasmuch as it is useful for the promotion and protection of autonomy for all. (Raz 1989: 1232)

Raz takes taxation to be coercive (indirectly) and argues it should be raised only subject to the terms of the harm principle. But the derivation of a perfectionist harm principle here cannot be based on any “global and indiscriminate” invasion of autonomy, because tax—except in extreme cases where imposed oppressively—does not attack autonomy that hard and, if suitably progressive, should leave the person taxed with her abilities to choose between an adequate range of valuable options intact (Stanton-Ife 2017). Of course, taxation, conceived in this way, does not imply what Raz elsewhere describes as “a coercive imposition of a style of life” (Raz 1986: 161). This seems to reveal that a much more nuanced account of coercion, in its various manifestations, is required, not that coercion “in this world” is always “global and indiscriminate”,

The second problem with Raz’s (correct) observation that coercion by criminal penalties can on occasion be “a global and indiscriminate invasion of autonomy”, is summarized in the question “what follows when it is?” What does follow, surely, is that such coercion must shoulder a large burden of justification. What does not appear to follow is anything to do with what kind of valid moral reason—be it harm-based or wrong-based—should be doing the needed justificatory work. The perfectionist starting point, as we have seen, is that there are no principled limits to the pursuit of moral goals by the law. It is the job of the harm principle to provide them if the harm principle can be successfully derived. Pointing to global and indiscriminate coercion points us to something that requires justification, but not yet to what kind of justification is needed.

As noted above Raz has another argument for liberal perfectionism’s right to claim the harm principle for its own: namely coercion

violates the condition of independence and expresses a relation of domination and an attitude of disrespect for the coerced individual. (Raz 1986: 418)

Might this argument make up the slack? Gerald Dworkin counters that coercing someone based on their wrongful or immoral behaviour need not show disrespect for such a person, “but merely for his conduct” (G. Dworkin 2007: 447). Alternatively, if it be accepted that coercion is disrespectful and expresses a relation of domination, one might again ask why that is not true of someone one coerces out of harming others as much as it is true of coercing someone out of some morally wrongful conduct? In both cases, does the legitimacy of the coercion not turn on the presence of sufficient justification, be that harm-based or wrong-based? Furthermore, if the key argument for the harm principle is really based on respect for independence and opposition to domination, it may seem particularly puzzling to identify how it is really a harm -based argument at all. It is true that independence, is for Raz, part and parcel of his understanding of autonomy (Raz 1986: 377–378); and it is also true that he understands harm in terms of setbacks to autonomy. However, if the argument turns on independence alone, the question arises of whether it does not collapse into—or keep sufficient distance from—certain principles devised in explicit opposition to the harm principle, such as Arthur Ripstein’s “sovereignty principle”? Ripstein argues that conduct should not be legally coerced if it does not wrongfully interfere with the sovereignty of others (Ripstein 2006: 231; for critique, see Tadros 2011).

Raz’s “one simple reason” why “the harm principle is defensible in the light of the principle of autonomy”, viz. that “the means used, coercive interference, violates the autonomy of its victim” (Raz 1986: 418) runs into the difficulty that often coercion does not do that or does not do that very significantly, let alone globally and indiscriminately. Furthermore, where coercion does violate autonomy globally and indiscriminately, it is either wrongful all things considered or justifiable only on the basis of strong valid reasons, which may include (exclusively) wrongness-based reasons for all that is as yet established. Finally, to the extent that the argument turns on independence it is not clear that harm is really doing the work.

As we have seen, several leading legal writers—be they in favour or against—continue to take Mill’s harm principle in original or modified form to be “the dominant theory as to what limits on criminal legislation should be observed by liberal democratic states” (Moore 2017: 461). Katrina Forrester’s post-war history of liberal political thought, however, emphatically puts John Rawls, rather than Mill, at the centre (Forrester 2021); and Piers Norris Turner, in an essay on Mill and modern liberalism, opines that public reason liberalism—whose leading light is Rawls—has become the dominant tradition within liberal thought “over the past three decades” (Turner 2017: 576; cf. Turner and Gaus 2017; Rawls 1999; Quong 2018; Hartley & Watson 2018; Freeman 2020). However, the growing and highly sophisticated literature on public reason among specifically political philosophers has not yet—at least not to the extent that it has in relation to legal moralism and the harm principle—received the sustained study of writers as heavily steeped in the law as Feinberg, Hart or Devlin. Specific legal applications of the public reason approach are, however, already in existence (for example Flanders 2016) and the approach continues to develop.

The approach suggests a different limit of the law: that laws must in some sense be based on public reasons , not reasons harvested from, or based on, comprehensive moral, ethical or religious theories. We saw above that while Devlin, Moore and Hart all supported the decriminalization of gay sex, they did so on very different understandings. Devlin did not rule out circumstances, admittedly extreme ones, in which criminalization might be justifiable in virtue of the intensity and comprehensiveness of the beliefs of ordinary persons in a society. Moore and Hart, by contrast, did implicitly rule out criminalization in such circumstances. Moore because the moral truth of the matter is highly pertinent, indeed decisive —there being nothing morally wrong with gay sex—Hart, despite assuming the moral truth of the matter to be irrelevant— gay sex is not harmful, so the conclusion goes through whether such conduct is wrongful or not. Rawls for his part would no doubt agree with all three on the correctness of decriminalization. But he would seek to exclude, as did Hart and Devlin, any Moore-style or perfectionist appeal to a comprehensive moral understanding to determine the issue. Devlin for his part would have had Moore down as one of the “moral rationalists” whose views he wanted side-lined in favour of the reasonable citizen.

In one way, then, Devlin anticipates a major preoccupation of Rawls. Rawls did not, to be sure, take Devlin’s apparent view that the moral beliefs of a society constitute (its) moral truth. His was not a scepticism about the existence of moral truth, merely a determination to avoid “the zeal to embody the whole truth in politics” (Rawls 1999: 132–133, emphasis added). But both Devlin and Rawls demanded that political power and legal coercion should be justifiable to those subject to them, provided they are reasonable. Thomas Nagel similarly insists a state’s law must do better than just tell those with certain conceptions of the good that they are mistaken, which seems the implication of Moore’s and of the perfectionist view; something more must be offered to them relating, he argues, to the point of view of such persons. According to him we must support:

… the exclusion of certain values from the admissible grounds for the application of coercive state powers. We must agree to refrain from limiting people’s liberty by state action in the name of values that are deeply inadmissible in a certain way from their point of view. (Nagel 1991: 155)

Devlin and Rawls, however, differed in how justification to reasonable citizens should be spelt out and it is here that Rawls develops much of his account. Devlin’s model of the reasonable person was the jury. To the question how the lawmaker is to ascertain the moral judgements of society, Devlin answered,

the moral judgement of society must be something about which any twelve men or women drawn at random might after discussion be expected to be unanimous. (Devlin 1965: 15).

To insist, as both do, that justification must be targeted at the reasonable citizen is to idealize the agreement on which their views were based (Raz 1990 [1994]; Enoch 2013; Billingham & Taylor forthcoming), since neither is saying one should simply seek the acceptance of (all) the citizens as they are, reasonable or not. Insisting on the actual agreement of citizens as they actually are is likely to prove excessively demanding, since too much of the rough must be taken with the smooth, accommodating misanthropic, misogynistic, egotistical, anarchic etc views. Devlin does not idealize a great deal, or at least he does not spell out in any detail how he understands what “reasonable” means, beyond insisting the reasonable jury-member must not hold “irrational” beliefs, such as “homosexuality is the cause of earthquakes” (Devlin 1965: viii). In stating one can notionally pick “twelve men or women at random” he appeared to think that a sample of the population is an adequate pointer to the appropriate morality. Here there is a stark contrast with Rawls. For taking a random sample of the population is to underemphasise moral disagreement, as Rawls would see it. It is not reasonable to think that moral disagreement will disappear in the medium- or even the long-term. And much of this disagreement cannot simply be blamed on the bloody-mindedness of some or on those biased in favour of themselves, their families, or groups. Some of the disagreement is based, rather, on differences over what evidence is appropriate, how much weight should be given to the evidence where it can be agreed upon, how priorities and choices should be made among the vast range of possible values and so on. Rawls describes factors such as these as “the burdens of judgment” (Rawls 1993: 56–57). Hence Rawls idealizes the constituency to whom legal coercion must be justified inter alia as the persons who accept the burdens of judgement and the resulting fact of reasonable pluralism.

The idealization involved in the public reason approach is controversial. There is scepticism in some quarters that there really is any genuine “middle way” between “actual (including implied) agreement and rational justification” (Raz 1990: 46). If too many constraints are built in, the very idea of justification-to a given constituency disappears. The leading natural law theorist John Finnis, writes:

Natural Law theory is nothing other than the account of all the reasons-for-action which people ought to be able to accept, precisely because these are good, valid and sound as reasons. (Finnis 1996: 10–11).

Natural law, theory, is a paradigm “comprehensive” doctrine, however, precisely what is to be avoided in Rawls’ view. If justification-to ends up meaning only giving good reasons to a certain constituency, the idea has all but evaporated.

Another contrast with Devlin’s members of the jury, is that Rawlsian public reason is not simply a matter of getting a sample of the people into a notional room and waiting for them to agree, however that is to be done. Public reason is itself a substantive framework to be shared by everyone, a module, “a complete political conception” whose principles and ideals are to be elaborated and whose arguments are to be deployed in legal argument (Rawls 1999: 138). It has content, in other words, “given by a family of reasonable conceptions of justice” (Rawls 1999: 132). While, as we have just noted, a natural law or Roman Catholic world view cannot itself be adopted under public reason, its conception of the common good or solidarity when “expressed in terms of political values” can be one grounding for a political conception that gives content to public reason (Rawls 1999: 142). For interesting explorations of the relationship between religious comprehensive doctrines and public reason, see, e.g., An-Na’im 2015, Billingham 2021.

Two kinds of issue of special concern to questions of the limits of law concern, first, the scope of public reason and, secondly, its capacity to account convincingly for certain apparently easy cases of legitimate legal coercion. As for the first, Rawls restricts public reason to “constitutional essentials and matters of basic justice” (Rawls 1999: 133). Is it convincing to thus limit public reason? In the eyes of some Rawls is too permissive about important matters of (non-basic) justice and fairness beyond the constitutional essentials and the basic aspects of justice. Jonathan Quong for example objects to Rawls’ openness to perfectionist values so far as “large resources to grand projects in the arts and sciences” are concerned (Quong 2011: 281; Stanton-Ife 2020).

Secondly, how well does the public reason view handle certain obviously legitimate uses of legal coercion, such as the criminalization of murder and rape? While there is no doubt that a Rawlsian public reason module, duly developed, would straightforwardly deliver the bare bones of coercive laws against murder and rape, can this be done fully and satisfactorily without the sort of recourse to comprehensive moral and metaphysical doctrines Rawls wishes to rule out? Take murder as an example. Standardly murder requires proof of at least causation of death with an intention to kill and penalties are among the severest, stretching in various jurisdictions to mandatory life imprisonment or, in some, to capital punishment. But how is “death” in “causation of death” to be understood? It is common to understand it in terms of the cessation of brain stem functioning. But why this understanding? For some putative victim may have irrevocably lost the capacity for consciousness while his or her brain stem continues to function. Is not the wrong of murder truly captured not only when the brain stem ceases functioning, but (possibly before that) when there is such “irrevocable loss of the capacity of consciousness” (Persson 2002; De Grazia 2017: 4.3)? For, one might say, it is the latter that explains what is horrific about murder. Someone who intentionally brings about the permanent cessation of the brain stem functioning of another should not be thought of as a murderer, the argument goes, where the capacity for consciousness of the victim is already known to have been irrevocably lost. Perhaps such conduct ought still to be criminal and labelled as such, only not as murder meriting the mandatory life sentence. The point for present purposes is not to settle the question of what the best understanding of murder should be, or whether the imaginary case should count as murder, only to suggest that these issues are likely to turn, implicitly or explicitly, on comprehensive moral and metaphysical understandings. Public reason will be insufficient-or so the challenge would run (Tadros 2012: 77). Somewhat relatedly is Rawls’ account of abortion—he argues for a “duly qualified right” on the part of a woman “to decide whether or not to end her pregnancy during the first trimester” (Rawls 1993: 243). Whether Rawls is entitled to this conclusion on the basis of public reason has been hotly contested (see the varying perspectives of George 1997 [1999: 209–213]; J. Williams 2015; Kramer 2017: 92–155; Laborde 2018; Chambers 2018; Arrell 2019).

In the Introduction a distinction was drawn between conceptual and evaluative questions about the relationship between law and morality; and it was said that the limits of law is generally taken to be a strictly evaluative question. The term “law” is generally left largely unanalysed, with the emphasis on the law’s coercive means and the extent to which it may legitimately be deployed in the pursuit of moral ends. But will be seen, there are some approaches sceptical of the distinction’s importance to our understanding of the limits of law.

It is uncontroversial to say that a (further) kind of limit of law is that contained in the idea of legality. Lon Fuller famously identified eight “desiderata” for laws. Laws should be general; they should be promulgated to their norm-subjects; and they should be prospective. They should be understandable (perhaps with professional help); the obligations they impose should be susceptible to being jointly fulfilled; and they should not require anything beyond the capacities of their norm-subjects. Laws should be tolerably stable and, finally, they should actually be upheld by the relevant legal officials, rather than ignored, bypassed or replaced by what the officials applying them consider more congenial standards (Fuller 1964; Rundle 2012: Ch. 4; Waldron 2016 [2020]; Sunstein & Vermeule 2020). Kristen Rundle and Jeremy Waldron both argue that the legal positivism of Hart and Raz, as well as a broader instrumentalism that would take in Devlin, [ 13 ] is too casual and accommodating in allowing the designation “legal system” and “law” to systems and norms that fall short on the criteria of legality (Waldron 2008: 14; Rundle 2012: 202). This implies that one cannot simply take the question of the limits of law to be an evaluative question. This would underestimate the extent to which supposedly conceptual questions about the existence of legal systems and laws are themselves evaluative questions. Hence the limits of the law should be seen squarely as both an evaluative and a conceptual question. Against this, while granting that conceptual questions matter and are themselves a large focus in the philosophy of law, one might wonder how far they matter to the specific issue of the limits of the law. If it is accepted for example that Fuller’s desiderata for legality or something close to them are indeed desiderata as well as to some extent conceptual features of the law (as does Raz 1977), does it greatly matter that one might conceive of such features as conceptual to a still greater extent ?

It is widely said by those sympathetic to the instrumentalist understanding of law that law is a “modal kind” rather than a “functional kind”, distinguished by its means (or techniques) rather than its ends; the moral legitimacy of such ends being contingent (Green 1996: 1711). In the words of John Gardner:

[T]o say that law is a modal as opposed to a functional kind is merely to say that law is not distinguished by its functions—by the purposes it is capable of serving. It is distinguished rather by the distinctive means that it provides for serving whatever ends it serves. Law is what Kelsen memorably called a “specific social technique” (Gardner 2012: 195–220, 207; cf. Kelsen 1941; Summers 1971).

The idea of the legal techniques , developed by Robert Summers, from both the positivism of Hans Kelsen and the anti-positivism of Fuller, points however to a line of thought about the limits of the law that is surely due a revival. The debate as it is mostly prosecuted is too dominated by the one “technique” of coercion. While giving coercion its due Summers also emphasized

educational effort, rewards and other incentives, symbolic deployment of legal forms, publicity (favourable or adverse), continuous supervision, public signs and signals, recognized statuses and entities
grants with strings attached. (Summers 1977: 126)

There is also growing awareness at a theoretical level of the importance of expressive values in the law (McAdams 2015). It is something of a loss that the schema developed by Summers and his collaborators, dividing legal techniques into “grievance-remedial”, “penal-corrective”, “administrative-regulatory”, “public-benefit conferral”, “facilitator of private arrangements”, appears to have fallen largely into disuse (Summers et al. 1986). For it allowed various areas of potential legal concern to be examined against a background of various legal techniques, coercive and beyond. Rawls’ question of how far such techniques should be subject to public reason is a further issue that might helpfully be pressed.

The law’s task, put abstractly, is to secure a situation whereby moral goals which, given the current social situation in the country whose law it is, would be unlikely to be achieved without it, and whose achievement by the law is not counter-productive, are realized. (Raz 2003 [2009: 178])

This remark could be taken as the essence of legal moralism. The basic core of legal moralism, as we have seen, is a two-part structure, compounded of a wrong and a set of countervailing and potentially defeating factors, such as liberty and privacy. From within legal moralism there are controversies over how morality should itself be conceived and controversies over how the first part of the structure should be conceived—all moral wrongs or only a subset of them?—and the second part—which countervailing factors, for example, make the list? And what, if anything, unifies them? While Raz’s remark may serve as a pithy statement of legal moralism, Raz himself rejected legal moralism, in favour of a version of the harm principle. Mill’s original harm principle was based on a monistic utilitarianism. There remain adherents of such a utilitarianism, but more influential today is some version of value-pluralism, such as Raz’s liberal perfectionism. The derivation of the harm principle from such pluralistic premises, is as we have seen, a far from straightforward task. Adherents of the harm principle also manifest a strong divide between those who broadly inherit Mill’s principled anti-moralism without his anti-paternalism, such as Hart and Raz and those who inherit both Mill’s principled anti-moralism and his anti-paternalism, such as Feinberg. Into the mix comes Rawlsian public reason. Like one kind of legal moralist, there is an emphasis on steering the justification of legal coercion to the citizens subject to the coercion themselves and from this an aspiration to develop a “module” of political practical reasoning, the public reason of all subjects of a given legal system independent of the comprehensive ethical or religious commitments of some of their number. For the proponent of public reason it is the “zeal to embody the whole truth” that is anathema (Rawls 1999: 132–133). To legal moralists such as Moore, the moral truth, with due sensitivity to the countervailing factors, should rather be the point. The idea that the law has sometimes no limits to hold back the moral truth—which of necessity must lie in the mouth of some (fallible) human—can induce a feeling of vertigo. Perhaps the question ultimately turns on whether there is a genuine alternative.

  • Adams, Robert Merrihew, 1999, Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0195153715.001.0001
  • Alexander, Larry, 2003, “The Legal Enforcement of Morality”, in A Companion to Applied Ethics , R. G. Frey and Christopher Heath Wellman (eds.), Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 128–141. doi:10.1002/9780470996621.ch10
  • –––, 2016, “Review of The New Philosophy of Criminal Law , by Chad Flanders and Zachary Hoskins”, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews , 2016.02.33. [ Alexander 2016 available online ]
  • Alexander, Larry and Kimberly Kessler Ferzan (eds.), 2019, The Palgrave Handbook of Applied Ethics and the Criminal Law , Cham: Springer International Publishing. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-22811-8
  • An-Na’im, Abdullahi A., 2015, “Islamic Politics and the Neutral State: a Friendly Amendment to Rawls?”, in Rawls and Religion , Tom Bailey and Valentina Gentile (eds), New York: Columbia University Press, 242–265.
  • Arrell, Robbie, 2019, “Public Reason and Abortion: Was Rawls Right After All?”, The Journal of Ethics , 23(1): 37–53. doi:10.1007/s10892-019-09280-8
  • Baehr, Amy R., 2021, “Liberal Feminism”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2021 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/feminism-liberal/ >
  • Barrett, Jacob and Gerald F. Gaus, 2020, “Laws, Norms, and Public Justification: The Limits of Law as an Instrument of Reform”, in Public Reason and Courts , Silje Langvatn, Mattias Kumm, and Wojciech Sadurski (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 201–228. doi:10.1017/9781108766579.009
  • Barry, Brian, 1995, Justice as Impartiality , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Billingham, Paul, 2021, “Can Christians Join the Overlapping Consensus?: Prospects and Pitfalls for a Christian Justification of Political Liberalism”, Social Theory and Practice , 47(3): 519–547. doi:10.5840/soctheorpract202169131
  • Billingham, Paul and Anthony Taylor, forthcoming, “A Framework for Analyzing Public Reason Theories”, European Journal of Political Theory , first online: 24 June 2020. doi:10.1177/1474885120925381
  • Blackburn, Simon, 1994, Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Brink, David O., 2013, Mill’s Progressive Principles , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199672141.001.0001
  • –––, 2018, “Mill’s Moral and Political Philosophy”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/mill-moral-political/ >
  • Brown, D.G., 2017, “The Harm Principle”, in A Companion to Mill , Christopher Macleod and Dale E. Miller (eds.), Oxford: John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 407–424. doi:10.1002/9781118736739.ch27
  • Carter, Ian, 2019, “Positive and Negative Liberty”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2019 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/liberty-positive-negative/ >
  • Chambers, Clare, 2018, “Reasonable Disagreement and the Neutralist Dilemma: Abortion and Circumcision in Matthew Kramer’s Liberalism with Excellence ”, The American Journal of Jurisprudence , 63(1): 9–32. doi:10.1093/ajj/auy006
  • Chiao, Vincent, 2019, Criminal Law in the Age of the Administrative State , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780190273941.001.0001
  • Conly, Sarah, 2018, “Paternalism and the Limits of Liberty”, in The Routledge Handbook of Libertarianism , Jason Brennan, Bas van der Vossen, and David Schmidz (eds), New York: Routledge, 427–435
  • Corvino, John, 2013, What’s Wrong with Homosexuality? , (Philosophy in Action : Small Books about Big Ideas), New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  • Curtice, J., E. Clery, J. Perry, M. Phillips, and N. Rahim (eds), 2019, British Social Attitudes 36 , London: The National Centre for Social Research. [ Curtice et al. 2019 available online (pdf) ]
  • DeGrazia, David, 2017, “The Definition of Death”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/death-definition/ >
  • Deigh, John and David Dolinko (eds.), 2011, The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Criminal Law , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195314854.001.0001
  • Delmas, Candice and Kimberley Brownlee, 2021, “Civil Disobedience”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2021 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/civil-disobedience/ >
  • De Marneffe, Peter, 2018, “Moralism and Moral Paternalism”, in Grill and Hanna 2018: 35–45.
  • Dempsey, Michelle Madden, 2009, Prosecuting Domestic Violence: A Philosophical Analysis , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199562169.001.1
  • Devlin, Patrick, 1965, The Enforcement of Morals , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Devlin, Patrick, along with Leonard Birmingham, et al., 1965, “Law on Homosexuals”, Letter to the editor, The Times (of London), 11 May 1965, p. 13, col. 4, issue number 56318.
  • Dickson, Julie, 2012, “Legal Positivism: Contemporary Debates”, in Marmor 2012: 48–64.
  • Donner, Wendy, 1991, The Liberal Self: John Stuart Mill’s Moral and Political Philosophy , Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • –––, 2008, “Autonomy, Tradition, and the Enforcement of Morality”, in Mill’s “On Liberty”: A Critical Guide , C. L. Ten (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 138–164. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511575181.008
  • Duff, R. A., 2007, Answering for Crime: Responsibility and Liability in the Criminal Law , Oxford: Hart Publishing.
  • –––, 2016, “Legal Moralism and Public Wrongs”, in Ferzan and Morse 2016: 95–110. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198703242.003.0007
  • –––, 2018, The Realm of Criminal Law , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780199570195.001.0001
  • Dworkin, Gerald, 1990, “Equal Respect and the Enforcement of Morality”, in Crime, Culpability and Remedy , Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, and Jeffrey Paul (eds), Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 180–193.
  • –––, 1999, “Devlin Was Right: Law and the Enforcement of Morality”, William & Mary Law Review , 40(3): 927–945.
  • –––, 2007, “Autonomy”, in A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy , second edition, Robert E. Goodin, Philip Pettit, and Thomas Pogge (eds.), Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 439–451. doi:10.1002/9781405177245.ch18
  • –––, 2011, “The Limits of the Criminal Law”, in Deigh and Dolinko 2011: 3–16.
  • –––, 2020, “Paternalism”, in The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 Edition), Edward N Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/paternalism/ >
  • Dworkin, Ronald, 1966, “Lord Devlin and the Enforcement of Morals”, Yale Law Journal , 75(6): 986–1005.
  • -----, 1977, “Liberty and Moralism”, in his Taking Rights Seriously , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 240–258.
  • –––, 1985a, “Do We Have a Right to Pornography?”, in R. Dworkin 1985c: 335–372.
  • –––, 1985b, “Can a Liberal State Support Art?”, in R. Dworkin 1985c: 221–233.
  • –––, 1985c, A Matter of Principle , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1996a, “Pornography and Hate”, in Dworkin 1996c: 214–226.
  • –––, 1996b, “MacKinnon’s Words”, in Dworkin 1996c: 227–243.
  • –––, 1996c, Freedom’s Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Edwards, James, 2014, “Harm Principles”, Legal Theory , 20(4): 253–285. doi:10.1017/S135232521500004X
  • –––, 2018 [2021], “Theories of Criminal Law”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2021/entries/criminal-law/ >
  • –––, 2019, “No Offense”, in Alexander and Ferzan 2019: 499–518.
  • Enoch, David, 2013, “The Disorder of Public Reason”, Ethics , 124(1): 141–176. doi:10.1086/671386
  • 1984, Volume 1: Harm to Others , doi:10.1093/0195046641.001.0001
  • 1985, Volume 2: Offense to Others , doi:10.1093/0195052153.001.0001
  • 1986, Volume 3: Harm to Self , doi:10.1093/0195059239.001.0001
  • 1990, Volume 4: Harmless Wrongdoing , doi:10.1093/0195064704.001.0001
  • –––, 1987, “Some Unswept Debris from the Hart-Devlin Debate”, Synthese , 72(2): 249–275. doi:10.1007/BF00413641
  • Ferzan, Kimberly Kessler and Stephen J. Morse (eds.), 2016, Legal, Moral, and Metaphysical Truths: The Philosophy of Michael S. Moore , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198703242.001.0001
  • Finnis, John, 1996, “Is Natural Law Theory Compatible with Limited Government?”, in George 1996: 1–26.
  • –––, 1998, Aquinas: Moral, Political and Legal Theory , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2000, “Abortion, Natural Law and Public Reason”, in Natural Law and Public Reason , Robert P. George and Christopher Wolfe (eds), Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, pp. 75–106.
  • –––, 2011a, Natural Law and Natural Rights , second edition, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2011b, “Hart as a Political Philosopher”, in J. Finnis, Philosophy of Law: Collected Essays (Volume IV), Oxford: Oxford University Press: 257–279.
  • –––, 2013, “Reflections and Responses”, in Keown and George 2013: 459–584. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199675500.003.0029
  • Flanders, Chad, 2016, “Public Wrongs and Public Reason”, Dialogue , 55(1): 45–58. doi:10.1017/S0012217315000074
  • Flanigan, Jessica and Lori Watson, 2020, Debating Sex Work , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780190659882.001.0001
  • Fletcher, Guy (ed.), 2016, The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-Being , London: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9781315682266
  • Forrester, Katrina, 2021, In the Shadow of Justice: Postwar Liberalism and the Remaking of Political Philosophy , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Fowler, Timothy and Zofia Stemplowska, 2015, “The Asymmetry Objection Rides Again: On the Nature and Significance of Justificatory Disagreement”, Journal of Applied Philosophy , 32(2): 133–146. doi:10.1111/japp.12090
  • Freeman, Samuel, 2020, “Democracy, Religion & Public Reason”, Daedalus , 149(3): 37–58. doi:10.1162/daed_a_01802
  • Fricker, Miranda, 2013, “Styles of Moral Relativism: a Critical Family Tree”, in The Oxford Handbook of the History of Ethics , Roger Crisp (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 793–817.
  • Friedman, Marilyn, 2003, Autonomy, Gender, Politics , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0195138503.001.0001
  • –––, 2005, “Autonomy and Male Dominance”, in Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism: New Essays , John Christman and Joel Anderson (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 150–174. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511610325.009
  • Fuller, Lon L., 1964, The Morality of Law , New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
  • –––, 1978, “The Forms and Limits of Adjudication”, Harvard Law Review , 92(2): 353–409. doi:10.2307/1340368
  • Gardner, John, 2012, Law as a Leap of Faith: Essays on Law in General , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199695553.001.0001
  • Gardner, John and Stephen Shute, 2000, “The Wrongness of Rape”, in Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence, Fourth Series , Jeremy Horder (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, ch. 10.
  • George, Robert P., 1993, Making Men Moral: Civil Liberties and Public Morality , Oxford: Clarendon Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198260240.001.0001
  • ––– (ed.), 1996, Natural Law, Liberalism, and Morality: Contemporary Essays , Oxford: Clarendon Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199243006.001.0001
  • –––, 1997 [1999], “Public Reason and Political Conflict: Abortion and Homosexuality”, The Yale Law Journal , 106(8): 2475–2504; reprinted in his In Defense of Natural Law . Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999, 196–227. doi:10.2307/797225
  • Gray, John, 1995, Enlightenment’s Wake: Politics and Culture at the Close of the Modern Age , London: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203933510
  • –––, 1996, Mill on Liberty: A Defence , second edition, London: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203432471
  • –––, 2000, Two Faces of Liberalism , Cambridge, UK: Polity.
  • Gray, John and G. W. Smith (eds.), 1991, J.S. Mill’s On Liberty in Focus , London: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203402283
  • Green, Leslie, 1996, “The Concept of Law Revisited”, Michigan Law Review , 94(6): 1687–1717.
  • –––, 2000, “Pornographies”, Journal of Political Philosophy , 8(1): 27–52. doi:10.1111/1467-9760.00091
  • –––, 2004 [2012], “Legal Obligation and Authority”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2012 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/legal-obligation/
  • –––, 2008, “On Being Tolerated”, in Kramer et al. 2008: 277–298.
  • –––, 2010, “Law as a Means”, in The Hart-Fuller Debate in the Twenty-First Century , Peter Cane (ed.), Oxford: Hart Publishing, 169–188.
  • –––, 2013, “The Nature of Limited Government”, in Keown and George 2013: 186–203. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199675500.003.0013
  • Green, Leslie and Thomas Adams, 2019, “Legal Positivism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2019/entries/legal-positivism/ >.
  • Green, Leslie and Brian Leiter, 2005, “H.L.A. Hart and The Concept of Law ”, Letters to the Editor, Times Literary Supplement , 11 March 2005, p. 15, issue 5319.
  • Greenawalt, Kent, 1995 [2016], “The Legal Enforcement of Morality”, The Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology , 85(3): 710–725; reprinted in his From the Bottom Up: Selected Essays , New York: Oxford University Press, 2016: 135–148. doi:10.2307/1144047
  • Griffin, James, 1994, “The Distinction Between Criterion and Decision Procedure: A Reply to Madison Powers”, Utilitas , 6(2): 177–182. doi:10.1017/S0953820800001552
  • Grill, Kalle and Jason Hanna (eds.), 2018, The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Paternalism , New York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9781315657080
  • Grimley, Matthew, 2009, “Law, Morality and Secularisation: The Church of England and the Wolfenden Report, 1954–1967”, The Journal of Ecclesiastical History , 60(4): 725–741. doi:10.1017/S0022046908005952
  • Hart, H.L.A, 1961 [1994], The Concept of Law , Oxford: Clarendon Press. Second edition, Penelope A. Bulloch and Joseph Raz (eds), 1994.
  • –––, 1963 [1982], Law, Liberty and Morality , Oxford: Oxford University Press; reprinted 1982 with a new preface by the author.
  • –––, 1967 [1983], “Social Solidarity and the Enforcement of Morality”, University of Chicago Law Review , 35(1): 1–12; reprinted in his Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy , Oxford: Clarendon Press, 248–262.
  • Hartley, Christie and Lori Watson, 2018, Equal Citizenship and Public Reason: A Feminist Political Liberalism , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780190683023.001.0001
  • Hurd, Heidi M., 2018, “Paternalism and the Criminal Law”, in Grill and Hanna 2018: 277–292.
  • Hurka, Thomas, 1993, Perfectionism , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0195101162.001.0001
  • Husak, Douglas, 2007, Overcriminalization: The Limits of the Criminal Law , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195328714.001.0001
  • Kane, Robert Hilary, 1994, Through the Moral Maze: Searching for Absolute Values in a Pluralistic World , New York: Paragon House.
  • Kekes, John, 2000, “The Enforcement of Morality”, American Philosophical Quarterly , 37(1): 23–35.
  • Kelsen, Hans, 1941, “The Law as a Specific Social Technique”, University of Chicago Law Review , 9(1): 75–97.
  • Keown, John and Robert P. George (eds.), 2013, Reason, Morality, and Law: The Philosophy of John Finnis , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199675500.001.0001
  • Kleinfeld, Joshua, 2016, “Reconstructivism: The Place of Criminal Law in Ethical Life”, Harvard Law Review , 129(6): 1485–1565.
  • Kramer, Matthew H., 2007, Objectivity and the Rule of Law , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511619014
  • –––, 2017, Liberalism with Excellence , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198777960.001.0001
  • Kramer, Matthew H., Claire Grant, Ben Colburn, and Antony Hatzistavrou (eds.), 2008, The Legacy of H.L.A. Hart: Legal, Political, and Moral Philosophy , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199542895.001.0001
  • Laborde, Cécile, 2018, “Abortion, Marriage and Cognate Problems”, The American Journal of Jurisprudence , 63(1): 33–48. doi:10.1093/ajj/auy007
  • Lamond, Grant, 2012, “The Rule of Law”, in Marmor 2012: 495–508.
  • Lammy, David, 2017, The Lammy Review: An Independent Review into the Treatment of, and Outcomes for Black, Asian and Minority Ethnic Individuals in the (UK) Criminal Justice System , 8 September 2017. [ Lammy 2017 available online ]
  • Lewis, David, 1989 [2000], “Mill and Milquetoast”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy , 67(2): 152–171; reprinted in his Papers in Ethics and Social Philosophy , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000, pp. 159–186. doi:10.1080/00048408912343741 doi:10.1017/CBO9780511625114.015
  • Lippke, Richard L., 2007, Rethinking Imprisonment , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199209125.001.0001
  • –––, 2008, “No Easy Way Out: Dangerous Offenders and Preventive Detention”, Law and Philosophy , 27(4): 383–414. doi:10.1007/s10982-008-9022-1
  • Lukes, Steven and Devyani Prabhat, 2012, “Durkheim on Law and Morality: The Disintegration Thesis”, Journal of Classical Sociology , 12(3–4): 363–383. doi:10.1177/1468795X12453270
  • Mackenzie, Catriona and Natalie Stoljar, 2000, Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Marmor, Andrei (ed.), 2012, The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Law , New York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203124352
  • McGrath, Sarah, 2019, Moral Knowledge , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • McAdams, Richard H., 2015, The Expressive Powers of Law: Theories and Limits , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Mill, John Stuart, 1859 [1993], On Liberty , London: Parker & Son; reprinted in Mill 1993: 69–185.
  • –––, 1861 [1993], “Utilitarianism”, Fraser’s Magazine , in three parts, 64: 391–406, 525–534, 659–673; collected and published as Utilitarianism , London: Parker, Son & Bourn; reprinted in Mill 1993: 1–67.
  • –––, 1993, Utilitarianism, On Liberty and Considerations on Representative Government , London: Dent.
  • Miller, Dale E., 2010, J.S. Mill , Cambridge, UK: Polity.
  • Moffat, Robert C.L., 2005, “‘Not the Law’s Business’: The Politics of Tolerance and the Enforcement of Morality”, Florida Law Review , 57: 1097–1133.
  • Moore, Michael S., 1992 [2000], “Law as a Functional Kind”, in Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays , Robert P. George (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press, 188–242; reprinted in his Educating Oneself in Public: Critical Essays Jurisprudence , New York: Oxford University Press, 2000, pp. 294–332.
  • –––, 1997, Placing Blame: A General Theory of the Criminal Law , Oxford: Clarendon Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199599493.001.0001
  • –––, 2014, “Liberty’s Constraints on What Should be Criminalized”, in Criminalization: the Political Morality of the Criminal Law , R.A. Duff, Lindsay Farmer, S. E. Marshall, Massimo Renzo, and Victor Tadros (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press: 182–212.
  • –––, 2016, “Responses and Appreciations”, in Ferzan and Morse 2016: 343–427. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198703242.003.0023
  • –––, 2017, “Legal Moralism Revisited”, San Diego Law Review , 54: 441–463.
  • Moran, Mayo, 2003, Rethinking the Reasonable Person: An Egalitarian Reconstruction of the Objective Standard , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199247820.001.0001
  • Mulgan, Tim, 2007, Understanding Utilitarianism , Stocksfield, UK: Acumen.
  • Mulhall, Stephen and Adam Swift, 1996, Liberals and Communitarians , second edition, Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Murphy, Jeffrie G., 1999, “Moral Reasons and the Limitations of Liberty”, William & Mary Law Review , 40(3): 947–957.
  • –––, 2006 [2012], “Legal Moralism and Retribution Revisited”, Criminal Law and Philosophy , 1(1): 5–20; reprinted in his Punishment and the Moral Emotions: Essays in Law, Morality, and Religion , New York: Oxford University Press, 2012: 66–93. doi:10.1007/s11572-006-9000-3
  • Murphy, Mark C., 2007, Philosophy of Law: the Fundamentals , Malden, MA: Blackwell.
  • Nagel, Thomas, 1987, “Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy”, Philosophy and Public Affairs , 16(3): 215–240.
  • –––, 1991, Equality and Partiality , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0195098390.001.0001
  • Nussbaum, Martha, 2004, Hiding from Humanity: Disgust, Shame and the Law , Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 2010, From Disgust to Humanity: Sexual Orientation and Constitutional Law , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Oberdiek, Hans, 2001, Tolerance: Between Forbearance and Acceptance , Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Packer, Herbert L., 1964, “The Crime Tariff”, The American Scholar , 33(4): 551–557.
  • –––, 1968, The Limits of the Penal Sanction , Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
  • Parfit, Derek, 1984, Reasons and Persons , Oxford: Clarendon Press. doi:10.1093/019824908X.001.0001
  • Persson, Ingmar, 2002, “Human Death—A View from the Beginning of Life”, Bioethics , 16(1): 20–32. doi:10.1111/1467-8519.00265
  • Petersen, Thomas Søbirk, 2020a, “A Soft Defense of a Utilitarian Principle of Criminalization”, Res Publica , 26(1): 123–141. doi:10.1007/s11158-019-09426-3
  • –––, 2020b, Why Criminalize: New Perspectives on Normative Principles of Criminalization , (Law and Philosophy Library, 134), Cham: Springer International Publishing. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-34690-4
  • Pickett, Brent, 2020 [2021], “Homosexuality”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2021 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/homosexuality/ >
  • Quong, Jonathan, 2011, Liberalism without Perfection , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199594870.001.0001
  • –––, 2018, “Public Reason”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/public-reason/
  • Rawls, John, 1993, Political Liberalism , New York: Columbia.
  • –––, 1989 [1993], “The Domain of the Political and Overlapping Consensus”, New York University Law Review , 64(2): 233–255; reprinted in The Idea of Democracy , David Copp, Jean Hampton, and John E, Roemer (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1993, 245–269.
  • –––, 1999, The Law of Peoples (with “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited”) , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Raz, Joseph, 1973 [1979/2009], “The Functions of Law”, Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence: Second Series , A. W. B. Simpson, Oxford: Clarendon Press; reprinted in Raz 1979 [2009]: ch. 9
  • –––, 1975 [1999], Practical Reason and Norms , London: Hutchinson; reprinted Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198268345.001.0001
  • –––, 1977 [1979/2009], “The Rule of Law and its Virtue”, The Law Quarterly Review , 93(2): 161–211; reprinted in Raz 1979 [2009]: ch. 11.
  • –––, 1979 [2009], The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality , Oxford: Clarendon Press. Second edition 2009. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198253457.001.0001
  • –––, 1986, The Morality of Freedom , Oxford: Clarendon Press. doi:10.1093/0198248075.001.0001
  • –––, 1989, “Facing Up: A Reply”, Southern California Law Review , 62: 1153–1235.
  • –––, 1990 [1994], “Facing Diversity: The Case of Epistemic Abstinence”, Philosophy & Public Affairs , 19(1): 3–46; reprinted in his Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics , Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994, pp. 60–96.
  • –––, 1996, “Liberty and Trust”, in George 1996: 113–130.
  • –––, 2003 [2009], “About Morality and the Nature of Law”, The American Journal of Jurisprudence , 48(1): 1–15; reprinted in his Between Authority and Interpretation: On the Theory of Law and Practical Reason , New York: Oxford University Press, 2009: 166–181. doi:10.1093/ajj/48.1.1
  • Rees, John C., 1960 [1991], “A Re-Reading of Mill on Liberty”, Political Studies , 8(2): 113–129. 29; reprinted in Gray and Smith 1991: 169–189. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9248.1960.tb01133.x
  • Rhode, Deborah L., 2016, Adultery: Infidelity and the Law , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Ripstein, Arthur, 2006, “Beyond the Harm Principle”, Philosophy & Public Affairs , 34(3): 215–245. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.2006.00066.x
  • Robinson, Paul H., 2000, “Why Does the Criminal Law Care What the Layperson Thinks Is Just? Coercive versus Normative Crime Control”, Virginia Law Review , 86(8): 1839–1869.
  • Rovane, Carol, 2013, The Metaphysics and Ethics of Relativism , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Ross, W. D., 1930, The Right and the Good , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Rostow, Eugene V., 1960 [1962], “The Enforcement of Morals”, Cambridge Law Journal , 18(2): 174–198; reprinted in E. Rostow, The Sovereign Prerogative: The Supreme Court and the Quest for Law , New Haven, CT: Yale University Press: 45–80.
  • Rundle, Kristen, 2012, Forms Liberate , Oxford: Hart Publishing.
  • Ryan, Alan, 1965 [1991], “John Stuart Mill’s Art of Living”, The Listener , 74(1908): 16–18; reprinted in Gray and Smith 1991: 162–168.
  • –––, 2008, “Hart and the Liberalism of Fear”, in Kramer, et al. 2008: 315–330.
  • Ryle, Gilbert, 1958, “On Forgetting the Difference Between Right and Wrong”, in Essays in Moral Philosophy , A. I. Melden (ed.), Washington, DC: University of Washington Press; reprinted in G. Ryle, Collected Essays, 1929–1968 , Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009: 394–403.
  • Sackar, John, 2020, Lord Devlin , Oxford: Hart Publishing.
  • Saunders, Ben, 2016, “Reformulating Mill’s Harm Principle”, Mind , 125(500): 1005–1032. doi:10.1093/mind/fzv171
  • Scanlon, T. M., 1975, “Preference and Urgency”, The Journal of Philosophy , 72(19): 655–669. doi:10.2307/2024630
  • –––, 1998, What We Owe Each Other , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Scheffler, Samuel, 1992, Human Morality , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0195085647.001.0001
  • Sher, George, 1997, Beyond Neutrality: Perfectionism and Politics , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511609169
  • Simester, Andrew P., 2012, “Enforcing Morality”, in Marmor 2012: 481–494
  • Simester, Andrew P. and Andrew [Andreas] von Hirsch, 2002, “Rethinking the Offense Principle”, Legal Theory , 8(3): 269–295. doi:10.1017/S1352325202083015h
  • –––, 2011, Crimes, Harms and Wrongs: On the Principles of Criminalisation , Oxford: Hart Publishing.
  • Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, 2019 [2021], “Consequentialism”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2021/entries/consequentialism/ >
  • Skelton, Anthony, 2012, “William David Ross”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2012 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/william-david-ross/ >
  • Stanton-Ife, John, 2010, “Horrific Crime”, in The Boundaries of the Criminal Law , R.A. Duff, Lindsay Farmer, S.E. Marshall, Massimo Renzo, and Victor Tadros (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press, 138–162. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199600557.003.0006
  • –––, 2012, “Preventive Detention at the Margins of Agency”, in Seeking Security: Pre-Empting the Commission of Criminal Harms , G.R. Sullivan and Ian Dennis (eds), Oxford: Hart Publishing, pp. 143–168.
  • –––, 2016, “What Is the Harm Principle For?”, Criminal Law and Philosophy , 10(2): 329–353. doi:10.1007/s11572-014-9311-8
  • –––, 2017, “Must We Pay for the British Museum? Taxation and the Harm Principle”, in Philosophical Foundations of Tax Law , Monica Bhandari (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 35–56. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198798439.003.0003
  • –––, 2020, “The Ends and Limits of Law”, in The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Law , John Tasioulas (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 208–234. doi:10.1017/9781316104439.012
  • Stephen, James Fitzjames, 1873 [1993], Liberty, Equality, Fraternity , London: Smith, Elder; reprinted Stuart D. Warner (ed.), Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1993.
  • Stoljar, Natalie, 2018, “Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URl = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/feminism-autonomy/ >
  • Stuntz, William J., 2000, “Self-Defeating Crimes”, Virginia Law Review , 86(8): 1871–1899.
  • Suk, Jeannie, 2009a, “Criminal Law Comes Home”, with commentary from Melissa Murray; Laura A. Rosenbury, Aya Gruber, Jennifer Collins, Cheryl Hanna, Emily J. Sack, Deborah Tuerkheimer, and Alafair Burke, in Criminal Law Conversations , Paul H. Robinson, Stephen Garvey, and Kimberly Kessler Ferzan (eds.), New York: Oxford University Press, 683–712. doi:10.1093/acprof:osobl/9780199861279.003.0031
  • –––, 2009b, At Home in the Law: How the Domestic Violence Revolution is Transforming Privacy , New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
  • Summers, Robert S., 1971, “The Technique Element in Law”, California Law Review , 59(3): 733–751.
  • –––, 1977, “Naïve Instrumentalism and the Law”, in Law, Morality and Society: Essays in Honour of H. L. A. Hart , P. M. S. Hacker and Joseph Raz, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Summers, Robert S., Kevin M. Clermont, Sheri Lynn Johnson, John J. Barcelo III, Doris Marie Provine, 1986, Law, its Nature, Functions, and Limits , third edition, St Paul, MN: West Publishing.
  • Sumner, L.Wayne, 2004, The Hateful and the Obscene , Toronto: Toronto University Press.
  • –––, 2011, “Criminalizing Expression: Hate Speech and Obscenity”, in Deigh and Dolinko 2011: 17–36.
  • Sunstein, Cass R., 2014, Why Nudge? The Politics of Libertarian Paternalism , New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
  • Sunstein, Cass R. and Adrian Vermeule, 2020, Law and Leviathan: Redeeming the Administrative State , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Swift, Adam, 2019, Political Philosophy: A Beginner’s Guide for Students and Politicians , fourth edition, Cambridge, UK: Polity. First edition, 2001.
  • Tadros, Victor, 2011, “Harm, Sovereignty, and Prohibition”, Legal Theory , 17(1): 35–65. doi:10.1017/S1352325211000024
  • –––, 2012, “Fair Labelling and Social Solidarity”, in Principles and Values in Criminal Law and Criminal Justice , Lucia Zedner and Julian V. Roberts (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 67–80. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199696796.003.0005
  • –––, 2016a, Wrongs and Crimes , Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199571376.001.0001
  • –––, 2016b, “The Wrong and the Free”, in Ferzan and Morse 2016: 79–94. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198703242.003.0006
  • Tasioulas, John, 2020, “The Rule of Law”, in The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Law , John Tasioulas (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 117–134. doi:10.1017/9781316104439.007
  • Ten, Chin Liew, 1972, “Enforcing a Shared Morality”, Ethics , 82(4): 321–329. doi:10.1086/291855
  • –––, 1980, Mill on Liberty , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • –––, 1991, “Mill’s Defence of Liberty”, in Gray and Smith 1991: 212–238.
  • Thomson, Judith Jarvis, 1986, “Feinberg on Harm, Offense and Criminal Law”, Philosophy & Public Affairs , 15(4): 381–395.
  • Timmons, Mark, 2013, Moral Theory: An Introduction , second edition, Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
  • Turner, Piers Norris, 2017, “Mill and Modern Liberalism”, in Christopher MacLeod and Dale E. Miller (eds.), A Companion to Mill , Oxford: Wiley Blackwell: 567–582.
  • Turner, Piers Norris and Gerald Gaus (eds.), 2017, Public Reason in Political Philosophy: Classic Sources and Contemporary Commentaries , New York: Routledge. doi:10.4324/9781315110868
  • Tyler, Tom R., 2006, Why People Obey the Law , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Velleman, J. David, 2015, Foundations for Moral Relativism , second edition, Cambridge: Open Book Publishers.
  • Waldron, Jeremy, 1987 [1993], “Mill and the Value of Moral Distress”, Political Studies , 35(3): 410–423; reprinted in his Liberal Rights: Collected Papers, 1981–1991 , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993, 115–133. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9248.1987.tb00197.x
  • –––, 1999, “The Irrelevance of Moral Objectivity”, in his Law and Disagreement , Oxford: Oxford University Press, ch. 8.
  • –––, 2008, “The Concept and Rule of Law”, Georgia Law Review , 43(1): 1–62.
  • –––, 2012, “How Law Protects Dignity”, Cambridge Law Journal , 71(1): 200–222.
  • –––, 2015, “The Rule of Law in Public Law”, in The Cambridge Companion to Public Law , Mark Elliott and David Feldman (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 56–72. doi:10.1017/CCO9781139342551.004
  • –––, 2016 [2020], “The Rule of Law”, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/rule-of-law/ >
  • Wall, Steven, 2013, “Enforcing Morality”, Criminal Law and Philosophy , 7(3): 455–471. doi:10.1007/s11572-013-9238-5
  • Wertheimer, Alan, 2002, “Liberty, Coercion, and the Limits of the State”, in The Blackwell Guide to Social and Political Philosophy , Robert L. Simon (ed.), Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishers, 38–59. doi:10.1002/9780470756621.ch2
  • Williams, Bernard, 1972, Morality: An Introduction to Ethics , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9781107325869
  • –––, 1975 [1981], “The Truth in Relativism”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , 75: 215–228; reprinted in his his Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973–1980 , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981, 132–143. doi:10.1093/aristotelian/75.1.215
  • Williams, Jeremy, 2015, “Public Reason and Prenatal Moral Status”, The Journal of Ethics , 19(1): 23–52. doi:10.1007/s10892-015-9190-9
  • Wolfenden Report, 1957, Report of the Committee on Homosexual Offences and Prostitution , Cmd. 247, London: Her Majesty’s Stationery Office.
  • Wong, David B., 2006, Natural Moralities: A Defense of Pluralistic Relativism , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0195305396.001.0001
  • Yankah, Ekow N., 2019, “Race, Criminal Law and Ethical Life”, in Alexander and Ferzan 2019: 625–648.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Stanton-Ife, John, “The Limits of Law”, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2021 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/law-limits/ >. [This was the previous entry on this topic in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy — see the version history .]

civil disobedience | coercion | consequentialism | constitutionalism | criminal law, theories of | death: definition of | feminist philosophy, interventions: liberal feminism | feminist philosophy, topics: perspectives on autonomy | homosexuality | justification, political: public | legal obligation and authority | liberalism | liberty: positive and negative | Mill, John Stuart | Mill, John Stuart: moral and political philosophy | nature of law: legal positivism | paternalism | perfectionism, in moral and political philosophy | pornography: and censorship | public reason | republicanism | Ross, William David | rule of law and procedural fairness | torture

Acknowledgments

I am very grateful to Les Green, Julie Dickson and the SEP editors for various kinds of invaluable help and to Joseph Raz, Liam Murphy, Grant Lamond, Dori Kimel and Alan Bogg for their helpful comments on the original version.

Copyright © 2022 by John Stanton-Ife < john . stanton-ife @ kcl . ac . uk >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Law and Morality

  • First Online: 14 December 2016

Cite this chapter

essay on law and morality

  • Willy Moka-Mubelo 4  

Part of the book series: Philosophy and Politics - Critical Explorations ((PPCE,volume 3))

1657 Accesses

2 Citations

3 Altmetric

Law and morality are two normative systems that control and regulate behaviors in a human community so as to allow harmonious and effective intersubjectivity between individuals who recognize one another as bearers of rights. Both notions have their common foundation in the concept of individual autonomy and equal respect for everyone. They have a complementary relationship. Law compensates for the functional weaknesses of morality and morality tempers the mechanical implementation of positive law through the notions of solidarity and responsibility. Different legal thinkers have interpreted the relationship between law and morality in different ways. On the one hand, there are those who argue that law and morality are independent – though not unrelated. For this first group, a law cannot be disregarded merely because it is morally indefensible. On the other hand, there are those who maintain that law and morality are interdependent. For this second group, any law that claims to regulate behavioral expectations must be in harmony with moral norms. Approached from this perspective, the law must be enacted in such a way that it secures the welfare of the individual and the good of the community. Thus, the aim of all laws should be both the attainment of the end of the state and the common good of the community, both immediate and ultimate. For Habermas, law and morality deal with the same problem: legitimately ordering interpersonal relationships through justified norms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save.

  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or Ebook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
  • Durable hardcover edition

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

John Christman, “Autonomy in Moral and Political Philosophy,” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy , http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/autonomy-moral/ consulted on Thursday, January 8, 2015.

Andrea Westlund, “Rethinking Relational Autonomy,” in Hypatia , vol. 24, Issue 4 (Fall 2009): 35.

Westlund, “Rethinking Relational Autonomy,” 40.

Christman, “Autonomy in Moral and Political Philosophy.”

Charles Taylor, “The Politics of Recognition,” in Amy Gutmann (ed.), Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994), 28.

Habermas, “Introduction to the Seminar on Jürgen Habermas’s Discourse Theory,” Ratio Juris , vol. 12, no. 4 (December 1999): 330.

Charles E. Curran, The Development of Moral Theology (Washington DC: Georgetown University Press, 2013), 74.

Michael Bertram Crowe, The Changing Profile of the Natural Law , cited by Alex E. Wallin, “John Finnis’s Natural Law Theory and a Critique of the Incommensurable Nature of Basic Goods,” in Campbell Law Review , vol. 35, no. 1 (Fall 2012): 60.

Legal dictionary, http://legal-dictionary.thefreedictionary.com/Natural+Law (Accessed, January 16, 2015).

Daniel Chernilo, The Natural Law Foundations of Modern Social Theory: A Quest for Universalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), 74.

Costa Douzinas, The End of Human Rights (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2000), 15.

Robert P. George, “Natural Law,” in Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy , vol. 31, no. 1 (Winter 2008): 172.

John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011), 280.

Finnis, “Natural Law and Legal Reasoning,” in Robert P. George, ed., Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992): 135–6.

Joseph Boyle, “Natural Law and the Ethics of Traditions”, in Robert P. George, Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays , 4.

Michael D.A. Freeman, Lloyd’s Introduction to Jurisprudence , cited by Alex E. Wallin, “John Finnis’s Natural Law Theory and a Critique of the Incommensurable Nature of Basic Goods,” in Campbell Law Review , vol. 35, no. 1 (Fall 2012): 62.

William O. Einwechter, Nature Law: A summary and Critique, http://darashpress.com/articles/natural-law-summary-and-critique (Accessed on December 22, 2014).

Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights , 35–36.

Jean-Pierre Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, vol. 1: The Person and His Work , cited by Stephen J. Loughlin, Aquinas’ Summa Theologiae: A Reader’s guide (London: T&T Clark International, 2010), 209.

Jacques Maritain, Natural Law: Reflections on Theory and Practice , ed., William Sweet (Indiana: St. Augustine’s Press, 2001), 43.

Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights , 28.

Robert Alexy, The Argument from Injustice: A Reply to Legal Positivism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 3.

Robert Alexy, “On the Concept and Nature of Law.” In Ratio Jurist , vol. 21, no. 3, (September 2008): 285.

Alexy, “Law, Morality, and the Existence of Human Rights,” in Ratio Juris , vol. 25, no. 1 (March 2012): 3.

Matthew H. Kramer, Where Law and Morality Meet (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 3.

Michael Giudice, “The Regular Practice of Morality in Law,” in Ratio Juris , vol. 21, no. 1 (March 2008): 95.

Andrei Marmor, “The Separation Thesis and the Limits of Interpretation,” in Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence , vol. XII, no. 1 (January 1999): 135.

Alexy, “The Dual Nature of Law,” in Ratio Juris , vol. 23, no. 2, (June 2010): 175.

Joseph Raz, The Authority of Law , 2nd ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 38.

Alexy, “The Dual Nature of Law,” 176.

Alexy, “The Dual Nature of Law,” 177.

Ronald Dworkin, Taking Right Seriously , cited by Raymond A. Bellioti, Justifying Law: The Debate over Foundations, Goals, and Methods (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992), 75.

Daniel Chernilo, “Jurgen Habermas: Modern Social Theory as Postmetaphysical Natural Law,” http://www.academia.edu/2638851/Jurgen_Habermas_social_theory_as_postmetaphysical_natural_law (Accessed on February 2, 2015).

Daniel Chernilo, The Natural Law Foundations of Modern Social Theory , 15.

Daniel Chernilo, The Natural Law Foundations of Modern Social Theory , 16.

Habermas, “Law and Morality,” 220.

Peter Bal, “Discourse Ethics and Human Rights in Criminal Procedure,” in Philosophy and Social Criticism , vol. 20, no. 4 (1994): 73.

Habermas, “Law and Morality,” 219.

Ibid., 223.

Bal, “Discourse Ethics and Human Rights in Criminal Procedure,” 73.

Habermas, “Law and Morality,” 226.

Andrew Edgar, The Philosophy of Habermas (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2005), 250.

I.O, 214–5.

Habermas, “Law and Morality,” 252.

Ibid., 264.

Ibid., 261.

Habermas, “Law and Morality,” 266.

I.O., xxxv.

Ibid., xxxv–xxxvi.

John Paul II, Sollicitudo rei Socialis , #38.

Ibid., 195.

Thomas McCarthy, Introduction to MCCA, vii.

Thomas McCarthy, “Kantian Constructivism: Rawls and Habermas in Dialogue,” in Ethics , vol. 105, no. 1 (October 1994): 45.

MCCA, 203–4.

Ingram, Habermas: Introduction and Analysis , 123.

Ingram, Habermas: Introduction and Analysis , 125.

William Rehg, “Discourse Ethics,” in Barbara Fultner (ed.), Jürgen Habermas: Key Concepts (Durham: Acumen Publishing Limited, 2011), 123.

I.O, Introduction, xii.

Habermas, “The Concept of Human Dignity,” 84.

Ibid., 452.

Ibid., 451.

Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologia , I–II, Q. 94, a. 2.

Ibid., 106.

Jürgen Habermas, “Law and Morality,”

Tony Honoré, “The Necessary Connection Between Law and Morality,” in Oxford Journal of Legal Studies , vol. 22, no. 3 (2002): 494.

Kramer, Where Law and Morality Meet , 117.

Exclusive positivism states that moral considerations must be excluded from the concept of law. As Didier Mineur notes, Raz contends that determining what the law is does not necessarily, or conceptually, depend on moral or other evaluative considerations about what the law ought to be in the relevant circumstances (Didier Mineur, “The Moral Foundation of Law and the Ethos of Liberal Democracies,” in Ratio Juris , vol. 25, no. 2, June 2012, p. 140). In line with Mineur, Michael Giudice notes that on Raz’s account it is never a condition of validity or existence of law that moral standards or considerations are satisfied. The existence and content of law always depend on what the official of the legal system actually practice as law (Micheal Giudice, “The Regular Practice of Morality in Law,” in Ratio Juris , vol. 21, no. 1, March 2008, p. 95).

Michael Giudice, “The Regular Practice of Morality in Law,” 99.

Honoré, “The Necessary Connection Between Law and Morality,” 494.

Habermas, “Law and Morality,” 259.

Ibid., 267.

Habermas, “Law and Morality,” 267.

Habermas, “Introduction to the Seminar on Jurgen Habermas’s Discourse Theory,” 331.

Ibid., 452–3.

Habermas, “Law and Morality,” 245–6.

Didier Mineur, “The Moral Foundation of Law and the Ethos of Liberal Democracies,” in Ratio Juris , vol. 25, no. 2 (June 2012): 142.

Alexy, “The Dual Nature of Law,” 168.

Ibid., 171.

Jerome E. Bickenbach, “Law and Morality,” in Law and Philosophy , vol. 8, no. 3, Symposium on Legitimacy of Law (December 1989): 291–2.

Bickenbach, “Law and Morality,” 295.

Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1978), 223.

William Rehg, “Discourse Ethics,” 120.

Rehg, “Discourse Ethics,” 120.

Rehg, “Discourse Ethics,” 121.

I.O, Editors’ introduction, xii.

Ibid., note 51, p. 274.

Arthur Scheller, Jr., “Law and Morality,” in Marquette Law Review , vol. 36, issue 3, (Winter 1952–1953): 320.

Alexy, Robert. 2002. The Argument from Injustice: A Reply to Legal Positivism . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar  

———. 2008. On the Concept and Nature of Law. Ratio Jurist 21(3): 281–299.

Article   Google Scholar  

———. 2010. The Dual Nature of Law. Ratio Juris 23(2): 167–182.

———. 2012. Law, Morality, and the Existence of Human Rights. Ratio Juris 25(1): 2–14.

Bal, Peter. 1994. Discourse Ethics and Human Rights in Criminal Procedure. Philosophy and Social Criticism 20(4): 71–99.

Bellioti, Raymond A. 1992. Justifying Law: The Debate over Foundations, Goals, and Methods . Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

Bickenbach, Jerome E. 1989. Law and Morality. Law and Philosophy , 8(3), Symposium on Legitimacy of Law: 291–300.

Boyle, Joseph. 1992. Natural Law and the Ethics of Traditions. In Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays , ed. Robert P. George. New York: Oxford University Press.

Chernilo, Daniel. 2013. The Natural Law Foundations of Modern Social Theory: A Quest for Universalism . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Book   Google Scholar  

———. 2015. Jürgen Habermas: Modern Social Theory as Postmetaphysical Natural Law. http://www.academia.edu/2638851/Jurgen_Habermas_social_theory_as_postmeta physical_natural_law . Accessed on 2 Feb 2015.

Christman, John. 2015. Autonomy in Moral and Political Philosophy. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/autonomy-moral/ . Consulted on Thursday, January 8, 2015.

Curran, Charles E. 2013. The Development of Moral Theology . Washington DC: Georgetown University Press.

Douzinas, Costa. 2000. The End of Human Rights . Oxford: Hart Publishing.

———. 2013. The Paradoxes of Human Rights. Constellations 20(1): 51–67.

Dworkin, Ronald. 1978. Taking Rights Seriously . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Edgar, Andrew. 2005. The Philosophy of Habermas . Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

Finnis, John. 1992. Natural Law and Legal Reasoning. In Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays , ed. Robert P. George. New York: Oxford University Press.

———. 2011. Natural Law and Natural Rights . New York: Oxford University Press.

Flynn, Jeffrey. 2003. Habermas on Human Rights: Law, Morality, and Intercultural Dialogue. Social Theory and Practice 29(3): 431–457.

———. 2009. Human Rights, Transnational Solidarity, and Duties to the Global Poor. Constellations 16(1): 59–77.

George, Robert P., eds. 2008. Natural Law. Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 31(1): 171–196.

Giudice, Michael. 2008. The Regular Practice of Morality in Law. Ratio Juris 21(1): 94–106.

Habermas, Jürgen. 1986. Law and Morality. The Tanner Lectures on Human Values (Harvard University, October).

Habermas, Jürgen. 1993. Justification and Application: Remarks on Discourse Ethics . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Habermas, Jürgen. 1995. Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between Facts and Norms. Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Habermas, Jürgen. 1998a. In The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory , ed. Ciaran Cronin and Pablo De Greiff. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Habermas, Jürgen. 1999. Introduction to the Seminar on Jürgen Habermas’s Discourse Theory. Ratio Juris 12(4): 329–335.

Habermas, Jürgen. 2001. The Postnational Constellation: Political Essays . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Habermas, Jürgen. 2008a. Between Naturalism and Religion: Philosophical Essays . Malden: Polity Press.

Habermas, Jürgen. 2010. The Concept of Human Dignity and the Realistic Utopia of Human Rights. Metaphilosophy 41(4): 464–480.

———. 2010. Rawls and Habermas: Reason, Pluralism, and the Claims of Political Philosophy . Stanford: Stanford University Press.

Honoré, Tony. 2002. The Necessary Connection Between Law and Morality. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 22(3): 489–495.

———. 2010. Habermas: Introduction and Analysis . Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

John Paul II. Sollicitudo rei socialis.

Kramer, Matthew H. 2004. Where Law and Morality Meet . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Loughlin, Stephen J. 2010. Aquinas’ Summa Theologiae: A Reader’s guide . London: T&T Clark International.

Maritain, Jacques. 2001. Natural Law: Reflections on Theory and Practice. Edited by William Sweet . Indiana: St. Augustine’s Press.

Marmor, Andrei. 1999. The Separation Thesis and the Limits of Interpretation. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence XII(1): 135–150.

McCarthy, Thomas. 1994. Kantian Constructivism: Rawls and Habermas in Dialogue. Ethics 105(1): 44–63.

Mineur, Didier. 2012. The Moral Foundation of Law and the Ethos of Liberal Democracies. Ratio Juris 25(2): 133–148.

Raz, Joseph. 2009. The Authority of Law . 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Rehg, William. 2011. Discourse Ethics. In Jürgen Habermas: Key Concepts , ed. Barbara Fultner. Durham: Acumen Publishing Limited.

Scheller, Arthur Jr. Law and Morality. Marquette Law Review 36(3): 319–327.

Taylor, Charles. 1994. The Politics of Recognition. In Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition , ed. Amy Gutmann. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Westlund, Andrea. 2009, Fall. Rethinking Relational Autonomy. Hypatia , 24(4): 26–49.

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Faculté de Philosophie, Université Loyola du Congo, Kinshasa-Gombe, Congo, Republic

Willy Moka-Mubelo

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Moka-Mubelo, W. (2017). Law and Morality. In: Reconciling Law and Morality in Human Rights Discourse. Philosophy and Politics - Critical Explorations, vol 3. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-49496-8_3

Download citation

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-49496-8_3

Published : 14 December 2016

Publisher Name : Springer, Cham

Print ISBN : 978-3-319-49495-1

Online ISBN : 978-3-319-49496-8

eBook Packages : Religion and Philosophy Philosophy and Religion (R0)

Share this chapter

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Publish with us

Policies and ethics

  • Find a journal
  • Track your research

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

The Role of Ethics and Morality in Law: Similarities and Differences

Profile image of Haxhi Xhemajli

2021, Ohio Northern University Law Review

The aim of this paper is to analyze the relationship between the complimentary concepts of ethics, morality, and law. To a certain extent, these related concepts share some common features. Ethics as a discipline is concerned with what is morally good and bad, and right or wrong, while morality deals with standards and rules of good conduct in society, and law, as a cognitive process, regulates social life through the promulgated rules crafted by a legitimate authority. But how are the differences or similarities between these interrelated concepts expressed? First, the main difference between law and morality appears in the mode of expression. Morality is expressed through the conduct of the individual and his relationship with others, whereas the law applies to the external behavior of individuals in their relation to one another as citizens. Morality is in some way an integral part of law, and every legal system, and to that extent is inseparable from it. Second, although ethics and morality are often used interchangeably, the difference between them, as we will examine further, is more than a matter of terminology, as the terms clarify the relationship of individual values to those within the social and legal order. Finally, regarding legal ethics, the importance of this discipline lies in shaping lawyers' behavior and professional conduct that are principles they should conform to as members of both the social and legal communities.

Related Papers

Legal Ethics

Kieran Tranter

essay on law and morality

Helen Kruuse

The South African legal profession has been subject to harsh criticism in the last few years, leading to what some have called ‘an ethical crisis.’ Although this perception may or may not be warranted, there have been numerous calls for improved ethical legal practices by South African lawyers. This article seeks to contribute to a discussion about the importance of implementing legal ethics education in South African law schools. The authors (a) explore the meaning of ‘ethical legal practice’ by reference to the international literature; (b) examine the way in which legal ethics has so far been presented in the limited South African literature on the topic; (c) argue the need for a more thorough and critical literature on South African lawyers’ ethics, coupled with a commitment to developing a stronger legal ethics culture within the profession and the legal academia; and (d) suggest a possible approach for South African legal ethics education in the future, with reference to recent developments in other countries

William and Mary law review

Lisa Lerman

In this essay, I contend that all clinical teachers should explicitly acknowledge that they are legal ethics and professional responsibility teachers and role models of the “good lawyer” in everything they do. I argue that every in-house clinical teacher should strive to make her clinic a model ethical law office.

Lawyers and the Possibility of Justice

Lynn Mather

Christine Parker

Cornell Law Review

john leubsdorf

67 Fordham Law Review 2377 2396

James E. Moliterno

International Journal of Clinical Legal Education

Leah Wortham

Externships or field placement programs involve students placed away from the law school and supervised by a person who is not employed by the law school. Externships offer many potential rewards for students as well as other stakeholders, including especially community institutions. But there are also risks—risks that the externship will be expected to accomplish too much with too few resources or that the externship program will be held back in the potential for contribution due to inadequate imagination or planning. This article seeks to encourage externship teachers to put aside assumptions that are sometimes made about how externship programs “should be” and consider some alternative approaches to course design and possible goals for externship courses.

SSRN Electronic Journal

Michael Krauss

Loading Preview

Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.

RELATED PAPERS

Robert Cochran

Hofstra Law Review

Andrew Boon

Julian Webb

Carrie Menkel-Meadow

Russell Pearce

Legal ethics (Oxford, England)

West Virginia Law Review

Barry Sullivan

Kim Economides

Elizabeth Keyes

Richard Moorhead

Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy

David Thunder

Clinical Law Review

arlene kanter

Robert Kuehn

William Mary Law Review

papers.ssrn.com

The San Diego law review

W. Va. L. Rev.

Ethan S . Burger

Louis Fisher

Bruce Green

Pace law review

Int'l J. Clinical Legal Educ.

SCLS Law Review Vol 4. No 1.

M Jashim Ali Chowdhury

Michael Ariens

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024

We’re fighting to restore access to 500,000+ books in court this week. Join us!

Internet Archive Audio

essay on law and morality

  • This Just In
  • Grateful Dead
  • Old Time Radio
  • 78 RPMs and Cylinder Recordings
  • Audio Books & Poetry
  • Computers, Technology and Science
  • Music, Arts & Culture
  • News & Public Affairs
  • Spirituality & Religion
  • Radio News Archive

essay on law and morality

  • Flickr Commons
  • Occupy Wall Street Flickr
  • NASA Images
  • Solar System Collection
  • Ames Research Center

essay on law and morality

  • All Software
  • Old School Emulation
  • MS-DOS Games
  • Historical Software
  • Classic PC Games
  • Software Library
  • Kodi Archive and Support File
  • Vintage Software
  • CD-ROM Software
  • CD-ROM Software Library
  • Software Sites
  • Tucows Software Library
  • Shareware CD-ROMs
  • Software Capsules Compilation
  • CD-ROM Images
  • ZX Spectrum
  • DOOM Level CD

essay on law and morality

  • Smithsonian Libraries
  • FEDLINK (US)
  • Lincoln Collection
  • American Libraries
  • Canadian Libraries
  • Universal Library
  • Project Gutenberg
  • Children's Library
  • Biodiversity Heritage Library
  • Books by Language
  • Additional Collections

essay on law and morality

  • Prelinger Archives
  • Democracy Now!
  • Occupy Wall Street
  • TV NSA Clip Library
  • Animation & Cartoons
  • Arts & Music
  • Computers & Technology
  • Cultural & Academic Films
  • Ephemeral Films
  • Sports Videos
  • Videogame Videos
  • Youth Media

Search the history of over 866 billion web pages on the Internet.

Mobile Apps

  • Wayback Machine (iOS)
  • Wayback Machine (Android)

Browser Extensions

Archive-it subscription.

  • Explore the Collections
  • Build Collections

Save Page Now

Capture a web page as it appears now for use as a trusted citation in the future.

Please enter a valid web address

  • Donate Donate icon An illustration of a heart shape

The authority of law : essays on law and morality

Bookreader item preview, share or embed this item, flag this item for.

  • Graphic Violence
  • Explicit Sexual Content
  • Hate Speech
  • Misinformation/Disinformation
  • Marketing/Phishing/Advertising
  • Misleading/Inaccurate/Missing Metadata

[WorldCat (this item)]

plus-circle Add Review comment Reviews

237 Previews

12 Favorites

DOWNLOAD OPTIONS

No suitable files to display here.

PDF access not available for this item.

IN COLLECTIONS

Uploaded by station61.cebu on May 11, 2022

Essay on Law and Morality

Students are often asked to write an essay on Law and Morality in their schools and colleges. And if you’re also looking for the same, we have created 100-word, 250-word, and 500-word essays on the topic.

Let’s take a look…

100 Words Essay on Law and Morality

Understanding law and morality.

Law and morality are two guiding principles that govern our society. Law refers to the rules created by the state, enforceable through punishment. Morality, on the other hand, is personal or societal beliefs about right and wrong.

The Relationship between Law and Morality

Law and morality often intersect, but they are not the same. Laws may be based on moral principles, but not all moral principles are laws. For example, lying is morally wrong, but not illegal unless it causes harm.

The Importance of Both

Both law and morality are essential for a harmonious society. Law maintains order, while morality guides personal behavior and social interactions.

250 Words Essay on Law and Morality

Introduction.

Law and morality are two integral forces that govern society. They influence human behavior and maintain social order, albeit in different ways. While law is a formal mechanism imposed by institutions, morality is an informal social construct, often derived from cultural, religious, or philosophical beliefs.

The Interplay of Law and Morality

Law versus morality.

Despite their overlap, law and morality are distinct. Law is objective, enforceable, and universal within a jurisdiction, while morality is subjective, personal, and varies across cultures. A conflict arises when a law contradicts personal moral beliefs. In such cases, individuals must decide whether to obey the law or their conscience.

In conclusion, law and morality are intertwined yet distinct forces that shape society. Their dynamic interplay creates a balance between societal order and personal ethics. Understanding this relationship is crucial in navigating the complexities of social life, and in fostering a society that respects both legal norms and moral values.

500 Words Essay on Law and Morality

Law and morality are two powerful principles that govern behavior and social structures. They are distinct yet intertwined, each influencing the other in complex ways. The relationship between law and morality has been a topic of philosophical debate for centuries, with scholars examining their interplay and the tensions that often arise between them.

Law refers to the system of rules enacted and enforced by the state or a governing body to regulate behavior. It is a formal mechanism of social control, providing a framework for resolving disputes and maintaining social order. On the other hand, morality refers to the principles or values that individuals or societies regard as right or wrong, independent of legal considerations. Morality is deeply personal and often grounded in cultural, religious, or philosophical beliefs.

The Intersection of Law and Morality

The law and morality intersect in many ways. Laws often reflect the moral values of a society, and moral principles can influence the development and interpretation of laws. For instance, laws prohibiting murder, theft, or assault are consistent with widely held moral beliefs about the sanctity of life and property rights.

Tensions and Conflicts

Tensions between law and morality can arise when the law either oversteps or falls short of moral expectations. Overstepping occurs when laws attempt to regulate personal morality, infringing on individual freedoms. For example, laws that criminalize certain consensual sexual behaviors or personal drug use can be seen as an overreach into the private moral sphere.

When the law falls short of moral expectations, it can lead to perceived injustice. For instance, when corporations exploit legal loopholes to avoid paying taxes, they may be acting within the law but violating moral principles of fairness and social responsibility.

If you’re looking for more, here are essays on other interesting topics:

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

essay on law and morality

The Relation Between Law and Morality

Introduction, works cited.

The connection between the law and morality is rather controversial as, on the one hand, morality must be separated from law and on the other hand, morality is an inherent part of the law.

The problem of law and morality is rather difficult, as many believe that there are no explicit distinctions between them. There are cases when morals coincide with true legal laws since humans created them. The human reason here could subconsciously shape the morality of law. However, the existence of unjust laws proves that morality and ethics are not similar. Therefore, the connection between the law and morality is rather controversial as, on the one hand, morality must be separated from law and on the other hand, morality is an inherent part of the law. In that regard, the film Trial (1963) is the confrontation of the natural laws based on morality and the juridical laws. In addition, the film also shows how the city creates its vision of the law system.

Law and morality must be separated as legal and moral standards are from being identical.

There is an assumption that law must be separated from morality due to the fact that legal and moral standards could not be identified. Closer attention to these issues was given from the angle of legal positivism. In his article, Hart expresses his radical view on the notion of legality based on social factors but on its positive outcomes. The author insists on the fact that law is neutrally colored; it could not be referred as to something bad or good. Considering this, Hart mentions that, “to enable men to see steadily the precise issues posed by the existence of morally bad laws and to understand the specific character of the authority of a legal order” (Hart 63). The Harts premises are based on the historical background and his referring to Austin whose theory of sovereignty. However, he rejects his idea of law based on the threat of punishment as it already includes the moral aspect. The theory of legal positivism implies that in the eighteenth-century people regard the law as separate from morality.

Hart also argues that the necessity to separate the law from morality is based on the presumption that morality could negatively influence legal standards. The fact is that the notion of morality varies depending on the mentality and culture of individuals. Then the law is the universal notion that comprises a limited number of moral aspects. That is why, the legal deviations are inadmissible since could be reduced to the subjective trial, as depicted in the Welles film under the same name. Hence, the main hero of the novel Joseph K. was taken under open arrest where he was forced to recognize the crime he did not commit. The film shows what consequences could be revealed under the impact of morality under the law and vice versa. The film also represents the corrupt system of law, which is unfair and ineffective. Joseph becomes the victim of demoralized law where the trial justice is handled by the human factors. Considering the film from Hart’s point of view, it teaches that the law should and must be separated from morality. Hart admits certain moral rights to be inserted into the legal system. However, natural laws must be excluded from the process of the creation of the law, as they may have negative outcomes for society.

Further, the movie contradicts Harts’s vision on the faithfulness of the law as it reveals the idea that law should also function as a means of moral satisfaction. The trial is a justice aimed at satisfying moral issues. Hart states, “Whether every particular rule of law must satisfy a moral minimum in order to be a law, but whether a system of rules which altogether failed to do this could be a legal system” (Hart 65). In this respect, careful consideration must have the command theory of law that reveals the falsity of separation of law from morality. To explain such a contradiction, Hart divides the laws of primary and secondary obligations. The theory discloses that there are cases that refuse the logical approach but are based on social aims, which are different in certain societies. Therefore, the law directly depends on society and its peculiarities (Hart 70). In contrast, the problem of morality and law arises when the cases are resolved without consideration of social situation but simply based on rational thinking.

However, Hart in his article considers that if a law violates moral issues it could not be regarded as the standard law. The same is observed in the movie when the main hero is trialed according to the specific laws based on the morals of the citizen but not on the universally acknowledged legal norms. Relying on this, Hart constitutes, “It could not follow from the mere fact that a rule violated standards of morality that it was not a rule of law; and conversely, it could not follow from the mere fact that a rule was desirable that it was a rule of law” (Hart, 64). Consequently, the city with his own vision on “law” contains his own vision of morals that considerably deviates the conventional views on ethics and human morale. The main protagonist could not accept the new surrealistic world where he is forced to obey the newly established rules. In the world of the imaginary rules he is accused of an unspecified crime; he is also arrested but not taken in custody. Anyway, this point of view shows the negative influence of morals on the law; at the same time, morality, in its good sense, is an inherent part of the law serving the ground of the legal concepts. In other words, the film proves that law is unlikely to be separated from morals on the mere ground that they were created by humans.

Law is considered as integrity as it identifies moral constraints and political morality.

There is an opposite view, where the law is considered as integrity because it identifies the moral constraints and on political issues. In the article Morality of Law, Lon Fuller expresses his own alternative view on the morale within the legal system. According to his article, Fuller represents two types of the morality of duty and morality of aspiration. According to this, “morality of aspiration starts at the top of human achievement, the morality of duty starts at the bottom” (Fuller 5). The former enlarges on the fidelity to the law that coincides with the adherence to positive rules. Fuller rejects Hart’s ideas about the law principle of adjudication where the law is fully subjected to the state. Considering this, Fuller presents “the internal morality of law” that serves to create just laws pertaining to society. Fuller’s idea of inner morality is rather controversial, as it does not the moral norms as something negative, like in the movie Trial.

Thus, the characters of the film create their own moral system that allows them to interrogate the accused Joseph K. during daily routine. Anyway, the film shows internal morality here is based on corrupt morality that converts the legal system into the distorted juridical mechanism infected by morals. Throughout the movie, where Joseph’s life is a mere trial, the leading character is constantly trying to justify himself in front of the trial for the crime he did not accomplish. His strange feeling of guilt proves Fuller’s theory of internal morality and fidelity to the law. Fuller identifies eight features that make the law fail. In that particular film, the law is distorted due to making the rules that contradict each other (Fuller 33). By this, the author expresses the idea of the availability of law. Hence, the inspectors and a useless advocate serve as the guardians of law that are directed against the good principles of morale. The film shows that morality can destroy the adequacy of law thus supporting Fuller’s idea that the law originates from the moral norms of a particular society.

Due to the fact that morality constitutes the law, there must be corresponding constraints. According to Fuller, the neutrality of internal morality identifies the objectivity of law. In other words, the researcher addresses the legal norms from the retrospective of “morality that makes law possible”. Therefore, only morality of duty but not aspiration must be applied to the legal issues. Here, the Trial is bright evidence of inappropriate legal issues that are based on moral desires but not on obligation. To support the idea, Fuller writes “as a citizen or as an official, [a man] might be found wanting. But in such a case he was condemned for failure, not for being recreant for duty; for the shortcoming, not for wrongdoing” (Fuller 5). The movie manifests that Fuller’s concept of the morality of duty as the basic rules for a full-fledged and just society without which, it would turn out to be a mess. The thrust of the trial lies in the fact that Joseph’s morality of aspiration does not coincide with the social norms.

It is worth saying that Fuller associates inner morality with the morality of the Old Testament and the Ten Commandments (Fuller 6). The above mentions the humans’ obligations to live according to social norms. Fuller shows that morality constitutes a person’s affiliation to a certain society and his/her determination as to the refuge of the community. One could not but mention the connection of God as the creator of law. The movie reveals the impossibility to enter the reign of God, as a man is not worth being equal with God. To put in other words, it is God that could punish and justify whereas a man has to obey. Here, we could observe that God defines the inner morality of each person abused by the government.

In conclusion, the opposed theories of Hart and Fuller reveal several dimensions of the film. From Hart’s point of view, the film Trial teaches why the law should be separated from the law; it also manifests a rigid distinction between moral and legal standards. By means of Fuller’s theory, it is possible to highlight the ground of the trial and Joseph’s uncertain accusation. The theory of two morality uncovers the points of the corrupt legal system of the city is motivated by the morality of aspiration but not the morality of duty. Anyway, both Fuller and Hart do not fully exclude morality from the law because the law is an obligation but not a desire.

Fuller, Lon. L. Morality of Law. US: Yale University Press, 1969.

Hart, Herbert, “Positivism and the Seperation of Law and Morals”. The Concept of Law, 1961.

The Trial, 1963, Orson Welles, Anthony Perkins. DVD.

Cite this paper

  • Chicago (N-B)
  • Chicago (A-D)

StudyCorgi. (2022, March 11). The Relation Between Law and Morality. https://studycorgi.com/the-relation-between-law-and-morality/

"The Relation Between Law and Morality." StudyCorgi , 11 Mar. 2022, studycorgi.com/the-relation-between-law-and-morality/.

StudyCorgi . (2022) 'The Relation Between Law and Morality'. 11 March.

1. StudyCorgi . "The Relation Between Law and Morality." March 11, 2022. https://studycorgi.com/the-relation-between-law-and-morality/.

Bibliography

StudyCorgi . "The Relation Between Law and Morality." March 11, 2022. https://studycorgi.com/the-relation-between-law-and-morality/.

StudyCorgi . 2022. "The Relation Between Law and Morality." March 11, 2022. https://studycorgi.com/the-relation-between-law-and-morality/.

This paper, “The Relation Between Law and Morality”, was written and voluntary submitted to our free essay database by a straight-A student. Please ensure you properly reference the paper if you're using it to write your assignment.

Before publication, the StudyCorgi editorial team proofread and checked the paper to make sure it meets the highest standards in terms of grammar, punctuation, style, fact accuracy, copyright issues, and inclusive language. Last updated: May 26, 2022 .

If you are the author of this paper and no longer wish to have it published on StudyCorgi, request the removal . Please use the “ Donate your paper ” form to submit an essay.

Last updated 10th July 2024: Online ordering is currently unavailable due to technical issues. We apologise for any delays responding to customers while we resolve this. For further updates please visit our website https://www.cambridge.org/news-and-insights/technical-incident

We use cookies to distinguish you from other users and to provide you with a better experience on our websites. Close this message to accept cookies or find out how to manage your cookie settings .

Login Alert

essay on law and morality

  • > Journals
  • > The Cambridge Law Journal
  • > Volume 71 Issue 1
  • > MORALITY, LAW AND CONFLICTING REASONS FOR ACTION

essay on law and morality

Article contents

Morality, law and conflicting reasons for action.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 March 2012

In The Concept of Law, H.L.A. Hart suggested that four formal features of morality distinguish it from law: importance, immunity from deliberate change, the nature of moral offences and the form of moral pressure. On closer examination, none of these supposed features clearly distinguishes morality from law, at least in the broad sense of ‘morality’ that Hart adopted. However, a fifth feature of morality mentioned by Hart – namely the role that morality plays in practical reasoning as a source of ultimate standards for assessing human conduct – does illuminate the relationship between law as conceptualised by Hart and morality variously understood. Because morality has this feature, law is always subject to moral assessment, and moral reasons trump legal reasons. It does not follow, however, that law is irrelevant to moral reasoning.

Access options

1 A.W.B. Simpson, Reflections on The Concept of Law (Oxford 2011), 1.

2 H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford 1961). References are to the 2 nd edition, edited by P. Bulloch and J. Raz and published in 1994. The 2 nd edition reprints the 1 st edition with the addition of a posthumous Postscript based on material written but by Hart but not published in his lifetime. The book has been translated into 17 languages, and more than 50,000 copies of the 2 nd edition have been sold since 1998.

3 The separation thesis must be distinguished from the thesis that there is no necessary conceptual connection between law and morality. Hart did not subscribe to the “no necessary connection” thesis. Indeed, it is inconsistent with the separation thesis, which entails that state law is necessarily subject to moral evaluation. Hart also believed that there is a “naturally” necessary connection between law and morality, which is found in the minimum content of natural law ( CL ch. 9). To mark the difference between the separation thesis and the “no necessary connection” thesis, some scholars now associate Hart with the “separability” thesis to the effect that law and morality are “separable” rather than separate. Concerning Hart's motivation in adopting the separation thesis see CL 207–212; see also Soper , P. , “ Choosing a Legal Theory on Moral Grounds ” ( 1986 ) 4 Philosophy and Social Policy 32 CrossRef Google Scholar ; F. Schauer, “Fuller on the Ontological Status of Law” in W.J. Witteveen and W. van der Burg (eds.), Rediscovering Fuller: Essays on Implicit Law and Institutional Design (Amsterdam 1999); L. Murphy, “The Political Question of the Concept of Law” in J. Coleman (ed.), Hart's Postscript: Essays on the Postscript to the Concept of Law (Oxford 2001).

4 The leading modern exponent of this approach is John Finnis: J. Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights , 2 nd edn. (Oxford 2011).

5 E.g. N. Simmonds, Law as a Moral Idea (Oxford 2007); L.L. Fuller, The Morality of Law (New Haven 1964).

6 E.g. R. Dworkin, Law's Empire (London 1986), 93: “the most abstract and fundamental point of legal practice is to guide and constrain the power of government. Law insists that force not be used or withheld … except as licensed or required by individual rights and responsibilities flowing from past political decisions about when collective force is justified.”

7 According to Martin Stone, it is the first, rather than the second, of these assumptions that distinguishes the separation thesis from soft natural law: “Legal Positivism as an Idea about Morality” (2011) 61 University of Toronto L.J. 313. He argues that (to the extent that law and morality share common concerns) soft natural lawyers think of law as a “part of” ( ibid ., p. 341) or, perhaps, an extension or realisation or concretisation of morality; whereas separationists conceive of it as an instrument or application of morality. See also R Dworkin, Justice for Hedgehogs (Cambridge, Mass. 2011), ch.19; concerning Kant's similar view see A. Ripstein, Force and Freedom: Kant's Legal and Political Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass. 2009), 223–5, 255–6. In Stone's account, for soft natural lawyers, morality is incomplete without law. By contrast, for separationists, morality is self-sufficient or, as he puts it, “self-standing” ( ibid ., p. 319). Stone particularly associates the separationist view of morality with the development of utilitarianism as a comprehensive moral theory and decision-procedure. The idea that morality can be fully understood without taking account of law pervades modern moral philosophy.

8 The topic falls between two stools: most philosophers who discuss the nature of morality are uninterested in law while legal theorists are typically more concerned with the normative relationship between law and morality than with the descriptive relationship.

9 Hart actually refers to “secondary” rules that empower the officials rather than to officials. But the significance of secondary rules is that they create and empower the institutions that administer the regime of primary rules.

10 Of course, there are many types of social institutions in addition to those identified by Hart as characteristic of law. In this paper, the terms “institutional” and “institutionalised” refer only to characteristically legal institutions. Ironically, Hart showed very little interest in actual legal institutions and how they operate in practice: Lacey , N. , “ Analytical Jurisprudence versus Descriptive Sociology Revisited ” ( 2006 ) 84 Texas Law Review 945 Google Scholar ; “Out of the ‘Witches’ Cauldron'? Reinterpreting the Context and Reassessing the Significance of the Hart-Fuller Debate” in P. Cane (ed.), The Hart-Fuller Debate in the Twenty-First Century (Oxford 2010).

11 For a suggestive discussion of the relationship between habit, custom and law see J.B. Murphy, “Habit and Convention at the Foundation of Custom” in A. Perreau-Saussine and J.B. Murphy, The Nature of Customary Law: Legal, Historical and Philosophical Perspectives (Cambridge 2007). For the criticism that Hart's account of custom is purely structural see A.W.B. Simpson, Reflections on The Concept of Law, p. 175.

12 Hart contrasted ideals with duties ( CL 182), aspiration and supererogation with obligation. It is not clear why he thought it important to include personal ideals in his account of morality since they have no clear analogy in his account of law, which is social, not personal, and rooted in obligation, not aspiration. Nor is it clear why he limited idiosyncratic, personal morality to ideals. An individual might, for instance, consider vegetarianism an obligation for themselves but not for others. Perhaps more importantly for present purposes, it is not clear whether or to what extent personal morality shares with positive and critical morality the four characteristics listed later in this paragraph – more especially, the last two. Social ideals have an important place in some concepts of law and certain accounts of the normative relationship between law and morality. See, e.g., the work of Simmonds and Fuller cited note 5 above. See also C.A.J. Coady, Messy Morality: The Challenge of Politics (Oxford 2008), 67–70.

13 R. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (London 1977), 53–58. See also G.J. Warnock, The Object of Morality (London 1971), ch. 5.

14 See also R.B. Brandt, A Theory of the Right and the Good (Oxford 1979), 172. It does not follow, of course, that social practices and institutions do not play a part – indeed, a very important part – in the formation of individuals' convictions and even their “personal ideals” (see e.g. P.F. Strawson, “Social Morality and the Individual Ideal” in G. Wallace and A.D.M. Walker, The Definition of Morality (London 1970)).

15 See also N. Cooper, “Two Concepts of Morality” in The Definition of Morality , esp. pp. 84–88. According to James Wallace, the philosopher John Dewey considered customary morality to be prior to critical morality: J.D. Wallace, Moral Relevance and Moral Conflict (Ithaca 1988), 73–6.

16 In Hart's revised view, the “social rule” or “practice” account of norms fails to provide “a sound explanation of morality, either individual or social” ( CL 256). The extent to which “morality” consists of “rules” is an ongoing topic of debate amongst philosophers that Hart does not address.

17 See P. Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals (Oxford 1965) (the Maccabaean Lecture is reproduced in Chapter 1); H.L.A. Hart, Law, Liberty and Morality (Oxford 1963).

18 As Bob Goodin neatly puts it: Goodin , R.E. , “ An Epistemic Case for Legal Moralism ” ( 2010 ) 30 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 615 CrossRef Google Scholar .

19 According to Hart, Devlin later reverted to the view that “the law [on homosexuality] ought to be altered”: Sugarman , D. , “ Hart Interviewed: HLA Hart in Conversation with David Sugarman ” ( 2005 ) 32 Journal of Law and Society 267, 285 CrossRef Google Scholar .

20 Following Hart's lead, in most jurisprudential discussions of the concept of law, morality is identified by its “form” as opposed to its “substance”. The substance of morality plays a larger role in theoretical discussions of particular areas of the law, such as criminal law and contract law.

21 Hart said much about what he called “the minimum content of natural law” ( CL ch 9). He argued that as a matter of “natural necessity”, both morality and law address certain obstacles to successful social life. The claim that morality is partly a function of human physical and mental characteristics and the natural environment in which we live is, no doubt, relatively uncontroversial; but how much of morality can be explained in this way certainly is not. For an expansive view see J. Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights , 2 nd edn (Oxford 2011). This is a key question in contemporary evolutionary and cognitive science. See e.g. R.A. Hinde, Why Good is Good: The Sources of Morality (London 2002); J. Mikhail, “Plucking the Mask of Mystery from Its Face: Jurisprudence and HLA Hart” (2007) 95 Georgetown Law Journal 733.

22 E.g. T.M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, Mass. 1998), 171–2.

23 “[I]t would be absurd to deny the title of morality to emphatic social vetoes” such as sexual taboos: CL 175. See also CL 182.

24 But not Devlin: Law, Liberty and Morality (note 17 above), pp. 19–20.

25 Ibid ., pp. 22–4.

26 Taking Rights Seriously (note 13 above), p. 255.

27 Ibid ., p. 248.

28 Ibid ., pp. 248, 250.

29 C. McMahon, Reasonable Disagreement: A Theory of Political Morality (Cambridge 2009), 9.

30 E.g. Simpson, Reflections , note 1 above, pp. 157–60.

31 B.Z. Tamanaha, A General Jurisprudence of Law and Society (Oxford 2001).

32 For a suggestive comment by Hart along similar lines see Sugarman, “Hart Interviewed” (n 19 above), 291. For a related point see Krygier , M. , “ The Concept of Law and Social Theory ” ( 1982 ) 2 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 155, 159 –61 CrossRef Google Scholar . By adopting a concept of morality as autonomous judgment, Neil MacCormick is able to establish a “conceptual” distinction between law and morality: N. MacCormick, Institutions of Law: An Essay in Legal Theory (Oxford 2007), ch. 14.

33 For an extended argument along these lines see J. Shklar, Legalism: Law, Morals and Political Trials (Cambridge, Mass. 1986), 39–64.

34 There are many versions and varieties of both moral realism and moral constructivism. My only concern here is with Hart's unwillingness to commit himself to any version of either. Christopher McMahon develops a view he calls “moral nominalism”, “intermediate” between realism and constructivism, to explain the important phenomenon of reasonable moral disagreement, to which Hart paid little or no attention and which, McMahon says, neither realism nor constructivism can adequately explain: McMahon, Reasonable Disagreement (note 29 above). Central to nominalism is the idea that moral ideas evolves and can change.

35 Because this phrase appears in the Postscript to The Concept of Law , I assume that by “moral principles” Hart means personal moral convictions as opposed to conventional morality. Hard positivists need not and do not reject Hart's view that conventional norms can be part of the law if the rule of recognition so provides: CL 44–8.

36 I assume for the sake of the argument that freedom of speech, equality, due process and so on are “moral” issues. However, it is arguable that framing the debate between hard and soft positivists in terms of the relevance of “morality” to the validity of law raises the stakes unnecessarily. Instead, the difference between the two positions might be said to concern whether the content of a law (as opposed to its source) can affect its validity. This reading of the debate is consistent with the argument made in the next paragraph below. In this light, a provision of the type we are considering would authorise judges, in assessing its validity, to take account of the content as well as the source of a law without raising any issue about the “status” of the relevant “substantive values”, for conformity with which the law is to be tested.

37 Hart may have been attracted to soft positivism because it seems descriptively superior to hard positivism. As a matter of legal doctrine, when legislation is held unconstitutional it is invalidated with retrospective effect, not deprived of effect prospectively. On the other hand, hard positivism is likely to be normatively attractive to those who distrust judicial power or who think that citizens should be able to identify what the law is without recourse to substantive moral reasoning.

38 Matthew Kramer is a soft positivist who commits himself to the view that there are objective moral truths and that it is such truths that the sort of provision we have been discussing incorporates into the law: M.H. Kramer, Where Law and Morality Meet (Oxford 2004), ch 2. However, he also accepts, of course, that judges are morally fallible. His view is that a judge who makes a mistake about what morality requires changes the pre-existing law while a judge who correctly identifies what morality requires applies the pre-existing law. Kramer argues that the interpretation of soft positivism I suggest here “can very easily be extended into an audacious form of rule-scepticism” in relation to the application as opposed to the ascertainment of law ( ibid ., 119). This conclusion seems to me to confuse moral reasoning with textual interpretation or, at least, to rest on a highly formal, rule-based understanding of morality.

39 J. Waldron, “The Irrelevance of Moral Objectivity” in Law and Disagreement (Oxford 1999). MacCormick apparently makes a similar point when he argues that for realists, autonomy is morally rather than metaphysically relevant to their moral lives (MacCormick, note 32 above, p. 250). Unlike Hart, MacCormick appears to have committed himself to some version of constructivism.

40 See e.g. Balcombe , Lord Justice , “ Judicial Decisions and Social Attitudes ” ( 1994 ) 84 Proceedings of the British Academy 209, 229 Google Scholar ; Bingham , Lord of Cornhill, “ The Judges: Active or Passive ” ( 2006 ) 139 Proceedings of the British Academy 55 Google Scholar , 70. For an extended scholarly argument to this effect see M.A. Eisenberg, The Nature of the Common Law (Cambridge, Mass. 1988).

41 Cane , P. , “ Taking Disagreement Seriously: Courts, Legislatures and the Reform of Tort Law ” ( 2005 ) 25 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 393 CrossRef Google Scholar .

42 Johnson , C.D. , “ Moral and Legal Obligation ” ( 1975 ) 72 Journal of Philosophy 315, 329 –31 CrossRef Google Scholar argues, with particular reference to promising, that in both law and morality importance is related to the level of abstraction and, conversely, specificity, at which their respective “requirements” are stated – the more abstract the more important, the more specific the less important.

43 Note 17 above, p. 22.

45 “Throughout the history of philosophy, by far the most popular candidate for the position of the moral point of view has been self interest”: K. Baier, The Moral Point of View: A Rational Basis of Ethics (Ithaca, NY 1958), p. 187. See also, e.g., S. Scheffler, Human Morality (New York 1992), ch. 2; Leiter , B. , “ Nietzsche and the Morality Critics ” ( 1997 ) 107 Ethics 250, esp. pp. 259 –60 CrossRef Google Scholar , 272.

46 See, e.g., M. Timmons, Moral Theory: An Introduction (Lanham, MD 2002), 134–5.

47 Hart treats this criterion inconsistently, in one place offering it as a point of similarity between law and morality, not difference: CL 172, where he summarises five “striking similarities between moral and legal rules of obligation”.

48 For the suggestion that the legal principle that promises should be kept is just as immune to deliberate change as its moral analogue see Johnson, “Moral and Legal Obligation” (note 42 above), pp. 322–4. In Johnson's view, the important distinction is not between law (changeable) and morality (immune to change) but between fundamental principles (immune to change) and specific rules and obligations (changeable).

49 Indeed, G.E.M. Anscombe famously argued that the concept of morality only makes sense within a religious framework: Ethics, Religion and Politics: The Collected Philosophical Papers of G.E.M. Anscombe, Volume Three (Oxford 1981, ch 4 (“Modern Moral Philosophy”). For a discussion of the role that authority might play in secular morality see S. Fleischacker, The Ethics of Culture (Ithaca, NY 1994), esp. chs. 3 and 4.

50 G. Harman, The Nature of Morality: An Introduction to Ethics (New York 1977), 112.

51 Of course, judicial reasoning is substantively constrained by institutional factors in a way that the moral reasoning of individuals is not.

52 To similar effect: Warnock, The Object of Morality (note 13 above), pp. 49–50.

53 More generally, this tendency may explain why philosophers deny the possibility of strict moral liability: Watkins , J. , “ Responsibility in Context ” ( 2006 ) 26 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 593 CrossRef Google Scholar , 606.

54 Wallace, Moral Relevance and Moral Conflict (note 15 above), p. 12. Wallace argues that solving moral conflicts requires active interpretation and adaptation of moral rules and principles in a way that changes existing rules and principles and generates new ones. Morality, he asserts, is “an intellectual and cultural achievement” ( ibid , 53) and a matter of “learned dispositions” ( ibid ., p. 55).

55 To similar effect: C.E. Larmore, Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge 1987), 149–50.

56 T. Honoré, “Can and Can't” (1964) 73 Mind 463; reprinted in T. Honoré, Responsibility and Fault (Oxford 1999). I am leaving aside the issue of causal determinism. Whatever the truth may be at the micro-level of physical processes, at the meso-level of practical reasoning and action there is no good reason to ignore the lived experience of freedom and control.

57 Fuller's famous list of pathologies of rules includes “requiring conduct beyond the powers of the affected party”: L.L. Fuller, The Morality of Law , revised edn. (New Haven 1969), 39.

58 At any rate, accounts of the morality of obligation as opposed to the morality of aspiration: see n 12 above. One exception that I know of is Bernard Gert's account of “common morality”, which he defines as “the moral system that most thoughtful people use, usually implicitly, when they make moral decisions and judgments”: B. Gert, Common Morality: Deciding What to Do (Oxford 2004), v. In Gert's scheme, the ultimate normative standard is “rationality” ( ibid ., pp. 91–5); and (he says) while it is never irrational to act morally, it may be rational to act immorally. Gert's view is explained by the fact that “common morality” is a substantive, not a formal concept. According to Gert, the basic principle of common morality is to “do no harm”. This understanding of morality also leads him to draw a distinction between religious principles about right and wrong, good and bad, virtue and vice on the one hand, and moral principles on the other ( ibid ., p. 4).

59 Cf Scheffler, Human Morality (note 45 above), p. 12: “a shared reference point for the formulation and adjudication of challenges to existing institutions and practices more generally”.

60 Or even that it is male or female: Criscuoli , G. , “ Is the Common Law Masculine or Feminine? ” ( 1981 ) 1 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 305 CrossRef Google Scholar .

61 For this reason, amongst others, Hart resisted classification of international “law” as (international) morality: CL 227–32.

62 In the philosophical literature there is much discussion of a different question of whether and the extent to which moral reasons for action override or, on the contrary, accommodate reasons of self-interest (and, perhaps, some other types of “non-moral” reasons). See note 45 above. There is a similar debate about the relationship between moral reasons and reasons of public interest: P. Cane, Responsibility in Law and Morality (Oxford 2002), 276–7; see also Hart's discussion of the relationship between “justice” and “social/public/common good” ( CL 166–7). The point I am making in the text assumes that the question of what reasons are moral reasons has already been answered. Under a theory that allows reasons of self-interest to trump moral reasons, legal reasons would presumably trump reasons of self-interest. One view of moral reasons for action is that they are “all-things-considered” reasons. So understood, morality would trump law as a matter of definition: Alexander , L. and Schauer , F. , “ Law's Limited Domain Confronts Morality's Universal Empire ” ( 2007 ) 48 William and Mary Law Review 1579 Google Scholar .

63 This way of presenting the issue will not appeal to those who think that all genuine reasons for action are moral. They might prefer a formulation in terms of a conflict of the moral reasons provided by the law and moral reasons apart from the law. See note 6 above.

64 Remember that this statement refers to the function of morality in individuals' practical reasoning. In a moral theory that distinguishes between conventional, positive morality on the one hand and individual, critical morality on the other, critical morality provides ultimate standards for assessing positive morality as much as other conventional normative systems.

65 Honoré , T. , “ The Dependence of Morality on Law ” ( 1993 ) 13 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1 CrossRef Google Scholar .

66 Even legal norms that are morally “arbitrary” in the sense that the norm chosen (e.g. drive on the left) is no more or less acceptable than some alternative (e.g. drive on the right) so that the choice between them is of “no intrinsic importance” ( CL 229–30) may provide moral reasons for action. Hart believed that morality “logically” cannot be arbitrary in this sense ( CL 229). However, if morality is understood not only to require and prohibit conduct but also to permit conduct that it neither requires nor prohibits, it is logically possible that in any particular situation several courses of conduct may be of equal moral value so that none is morally preferable to any alternative.

67 I hope that this account of the relationship between law and moral reasoning, both “everyday” and “philosophical”, is an improvement on the account I gave in Responsibility in Law and Morality , which was fairly criticised by Watkins , Jeremy , “ Responsibility in Context ” ( 2006 ) 26 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 593 CrossRef Google Scholar .

68 I am not sure whether Alexander and Schauer (note 62 above) go quite as far as this.

69 Finnis, op. cit. note 4 above, p. 14.

70 Simmonds, op. cit. note 5 above.

Crossref logo

This article has been cited by the following publications. This list is generated based on data provided by Crossref .

  • Google Scholar

View all Google Scholar citations for this article.

Save article to Kindle

To save this article to your Kindle, first ensure [email protected] is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle .

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Volume 71, Issue 1
  • Peter Cane (a1)
  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0008197312000207

Save article to Dropbox

To save this article to your Dropbox account, please select one or more formats and confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you used this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your Dropbox account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox .

Save article to Google Drive

To save this article to your Google Drive account, please select one or more formats and confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you used this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your Google Drive account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive .

Reply to: Submit a response

- No HTML tags allowed - Web page URLs will display as text only - Lines and paragraphs break automatically - Attachments, images or tables are not permitted

Your details

Your email address will be used in order to notify you when your comment has been reviewed by the moderator and in case the author(s) of the article or the moderator need to contact you directly.

You have entered the maximum number of contributors

Conflicting interests.

Please list any fees and grants from, employment by, consultancy for, shared ownership in or any close relationship with, at any time over the preceding 36 months, any organisation whose interests may be affected by the publication of the response. Please also list any non-financial associations or interests (personal, professional, political, institutional, religious or other) that a reasonable reader would want to know about in relation to the submitted work. This pertains to all the authors of the piece, their spouses or partners.

An Open Letter to Law Students on the Death Penalty

14 Pages Posted: 11 Jul 2024

Jesse Cheng

DePaul University - College of Law

Helen Prejean

DePaul University

Date Written: July 03, 2024

This open letter to law students discusses the Model Penal Code's retraction of its provisions on death penalty procedure, with an emphasis on moral implications that are relevant to all future members of the bar. 

Keywords: death penalty, mitigation, aggravation, Model Penal Code, procedure

Suggested Citation: Suggested Citation

Jesse Cheng (Contact Author)

Depaul university - college of law ( email ).

25 E. Jackson Blvd. Chicago, IL 60604-2287 United States

DePaul University ( email )

Do you have a job opening that you would like to promote on ssrn, paper statistics, related ejournals, u.s. constitutional law: rights & liberties ejournal.

Subscribe to this fee journal for more curated articles on this topic

Litigation & Procedure eJournal

Criminal law ejournal, criminal procedure ejournal, corrections & sentencing law & policy ejournal, criminal law, courts & procedure ejournal, corrections & rehabilitation ejournal.

  • Search Menu

Sign in through your institution

  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Urban Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Residential and Domestic Buildings
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Numismatics
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Social History
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Learning (Specific Skills)
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Acquisition
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethics in Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Religion
  • Music and Media
  • Music and Culture
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Construction Law
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Politics
  • Law and Society
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Study and Revision
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Neuroanaesthesia
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Medical Oncology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Medical Ethics
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Self-help and Personal Development
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Cell Biology
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Graphical and Digital Media Applications
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Electronics and Communications Engineering
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Ceramics and Glasses
  • Composite Materials
  • Metals, Alloying, and Corrosion
  • Nanotechnology
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business Strategy
  • Business Ethics
  • Business History
  • Business and Government
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Social Issues in Business and Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic History
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Applied Ecology (Social Science)
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Sustainability
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • Ethnic Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • International Political Economy
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Political Theory
  • Politics and Law
  • Politics of Development
  • Public Administration
  • Public Policy
  • Qualitative Political Methodology
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • East Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Land Forces and Warfare
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Naval Forces and Warfare
  • Other Warfare and Defence Issues
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution
  • Weapons and Equipment

Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics

  • < Previous chapter
  • Next chapter >

Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics

10 Authority, Law, and Morality

  • Published: August 1995
  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

Three theses with clear implications concerning the relation between law and morality have been defended in recent years: the sources thesis, the incorporation thesis, and the coherence thesis. This chapter defends the sources thesis against some common misunderstandings, and provides a reason for preferring it to the other two. The argument turns on the nature of authority, which is the subject of the first section. The second section shows the relevance of some of the implications of the analysis to the understanding of the law. Their relation with the three theses is then examined in the next three sections that follow. The last section concludes with some observations concerning the relations between legal theory, law, and morality.

Personal account

  • Sign in with email/username & password
  • Get email alerts
  • Save searches
  • Purchase content
  • Activate your purchase/trial code
  • Add your ORCID iD

Institutional access

Sign in with a library card.

  • Sign in with username/password
  • Recommend to your librarian
  • Institutional account management
  • Get help with access

Access to content on Oxford Academic is often provided through institutional subscriptions and purchases. If you are a member of an institution with an active account, you may be able to access content in one of the following ways:

IP based access

Typically, access is provided across an institutional network to a range of IP addresses. This authentication occurs automatically, and it is not possible to sign out of an IP authenticated account.

Choose this option to get remote access when outside your institution. Shibboleth/Open Athens technology is used to provide single sign-on between your institution’s website and Oxford Academic.

  • Click Sign in through your institution.
  • Select your institution from the list provided, which will take you to your institution's website to sign in.
  • When on the institution site, please use the credentials provided by your institution. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.
  • Following successful sign in, you will be returned to Oxford Academic.

If your institution is not listed or you cannot sign in to your institution’s website, please contact your librarian or administrator.

Enter your library card number to sign in. If you cannot sign in, please contact your librarian.

Society Members

Society member access to a journal is achieved in one of the following ways:

Sign in through society site

Many societies offer single sign-on between the society website and Oxford Academic. If you see ‘Sign in through society site’ in the sign in pane within a journal:

  • Click Sign in through society site.
  • When on the society site, please use the credentials provided by that society. Do not use an Oxford Academic personal account.

If you do not have a society account or have forgotten your username or password, please contact your society.

Sign in using a personal account

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members. See below.

A personal account can be used to get email alerts, save searches, purchase content, and activate subscriptions.

Some societies use Oxford Academic personal accounts to provide access to their members.

Viewing your signed in accounts

Click the account icon in the top right to:

  • View your signed in personal account and access account management features.
  • View the institutional accounts that are providing access.

Signed in but can't access content

Oxford Academic is home to a wide variety of products. The institutional subscription may not cover the content that you are trying to access. If you believe you should have access to that content, please contact your librarian.

For librarians and administrators, your personal account also provides access to institutional account management. Here you will find options to view and activate subscriptions, manage institutional settings and access options, access usage statistics, and more.

Our books are available by subscription or purchase to libraries and institutions.

Month: Total Views:
October 2022 156
November 2022 76
December 2022 53
January 2023 140
February 2023 177
March 2023 109
April 2023 154
May 2023 244
June 2023 198
July 2023 91
August 2023 133
September 2023 86
October 2023 99
November 2023 152
December 2023 69
January 2024 114
February 2024 410
March 2024 234
April 2024 205
May 2024 308
June 2024 105
July 2024 5
  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Rights and permissions
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

New York Times editorial board calls Donald Trump 'unfit to lead,' urges voters to reject reelection bid

essay on law and morality

WASHINGTON - The New York Times' editorial boar d called on voters to reject Donald Trump' s reelection bid, alleging that the former president is "unfit to lead" a second term. 

“Mr. Trump has shown a character unworthy of the responsibilities of the presidency. He has demonstrated an utter lack of respect for the Constitution, the rule of law and the American people,” wrote the Times editorial board, made up of opinion journalists, in a piece published Thursday.

“Instead of a cogent vision for the country’s future, Mr. Trump is animated by a thirst for political power: to use the levers of government to advance his interests, satisfy his impulses and exact retribution against those who he thinks have wronged him,” they added. 

In the piece, the editorial board outlined five “essential” qualities and values that they feel a president must have - and that they say Trump fails on: moral fitness, principled leadership, character, a president’s words and rule of law.

“We urge voters to see the dangers of a second Trump term clearly and to reject it,” they wrote. 

Last month, the New York Times editorial board published a piece calling on President Joe Biden to drop out of the 2024 race following a disastrous debate performance. The president struggled to complete sentences during the showdown and articulate his pitch to voters.

The Times argued in its op-ed piece at the time that "the president is engaged in a reckless gamble," adding that "it's too big a bet to simply hope Americans will overlook or discount Mr. Biden's age and infirmity that they see with their own eyes."

Since the debate, a growing handful of Democratic lawmakers have called on Biden to pass the torch and exit the 2024 race for the White House.

Rep. Hillary Scholten, D-Mich., on Thursday became the 10th House member to publicly call for Biden to leave the presidential race, adding to the drip of lawmakers pushing for change.

Contributing: Riley Beggin, USA TODAY

COMMENTS

  1. The Morality and Law Relationship

    Introduction. Moral principles are the backbone of society. In the process of establishing rules and hierarchies to follow, people have chosen certain principles and beliefs that are beneficial to them as a group. Common taboos such as killing or stealing are understood as detrimental to social life, creating an incentive to prevent people from ...

  2. The authority of law: Essays on law and morality

    Abstract. This revised edition of one of the classic works of modern legal philosophy, first published in 1979, represents the author's contribution which has had an enduring influence on philosophical work on the nature of law and its relation to morality. The new edition includes two previously uncollected essays and a new introduction from ...

  3. Law and morality

    Law can be defined as a body of rules and principles of procedure and conduct established and enforced by a political authority. Morality can be defined as a code of conduct advanced by a society or religion or adopted by an individual to guide his or her own behaviour [1]. In essence, as Kant asserts in Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals ...

  4. 1 Relationships Between Law and Morality

    This chapter distinguishes three types of inquiry about law. It articulates the two conceptual views about morality and the nature of law that comprise the focus of this volume. First, the chapter explains positivist and anti-positivist views with respect to whether it is a conceptual truth that the criteria of legal validity include moral ...

  5. Law and morality

    Moral questions inexorably arise in almost any legal system, and confronting them is one of the fundamental characteristics of a free society. 'Law and morality' examines the relationship between the law and the moral practices adopted by society. In some cases, there is conflict between the law and the moral code of certain individuals or ...

  6. The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality

    This classic collection of essays, first published in 1979, has had an enduring influence on philosophical work on the nature of law and its relation to morality. Raz begins by presenting an analysis of the concept of authority and what is involved in law's claim to moral authority. He then develops a detailed explanation of the nature of law and legal systems, presenting a seminal argument ...

  7. The Limits of Law

    The Limits of Law. First published Sat Jan 29, 2022. A central—perhaps the central—question of the philosophy of law concerns the relationship between law and morality. The concern breaks down into many issues, both conceptual and evaluative. Among the evaluative issues is the question of obedience to law: does the fact that some norm is a ...

  8. Law and Morality

    Law and morality are two normative systems that control and regulate behaviors in a human community so as to allow harmonious and effective intersubjectivity between individuals who recognize one another as bearers of rights. ... Natural Law and Legal Reasoning. In Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays, ed. Robert P. George. New York: Oxford ...

  9. (PDF) The Role of Ethics and Morality in Law: Similarities and

    JOSEPH RAZ, ETHICS IN THE PUBLIC DOMAIN, ESSAYS IN THE MORALITY OF LAW AND POLITICS 210 (rev. ed. 1995). Raz further states the three thesis with clear implications concerning the relation between law and morality, that are: (1) The source thesis: All law is sourced based; (2) The incorporation thesis: All law is either sourced-based or ...

  10. The authority of law : essays on law and morality

    The authority of law : essays on law and morality Bookreader Item Preview ... Law -- Philosophy, Legal positivism, Natural law, Law and ethics Publisher Oxford : Clarendon Press ; New York : Oxford University Press Collection internetarchivebooks; printdisabled; inlibrary Contributor

  11. The Authority of Law : Essays on Law and Morality

    This classic collection of essays, first published in 1979, has had an enduring influence on philosophical work on the nature of law and its relation to morality. Raz begins by presenting an analysis of the concept of authority and what is involved in law's claim to moral authority. He then develops a detailed explanation of the nature of law and legal systems, presenting a seminal argument ...

  12. Laws Relation to Morality

    Law's relation to morality has been debated ever since Jurisprudence itself came to be, and it seems as though it is destined to remain as one of the great philosophical debates. The question of the 'common good' though is slightly more specific than that of just morality, and obviously will require a definition of the common good itself.

  13. Essay on Law and Morality

    250 Words Essay on Law and Morality Introduction. Law and morality are two integral forces that govern society. They influence human behavior and maintain social order, albeit in different ways. While law is a formal mechanism imposed by institutions, morality is an informal social construct, often derived from cultural, religious, or ...

  14. Essay on Relationship Between Law and Morality

    1268 Words. 6 Pages. Open Document. In this essay I intend to discuss the relationship between law and morality through the perspectives of legal philosophers, I will provide a brief explanation of law, and what does law intend to achieve in the society. When discussing the relationship between law and morality I will consider the distinction ...

  15. Should There Be Morality in the Law?

    H.L.A Hart: Within Hart's theory, he maintains that Law and Morality should remain separate. In one of his most famous works; 'The Concept of Law [1] ' he analysis' the relation between that is between law, coercion and morality. In order to try to and clarify whether laws are coercive orders or moral commands.

  16. Law and Moral Obligation

    Law and Moral Obligation. Law and Moral Obligation. Patricia D. Whitet The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality. JOSEPH RAz. The Clarendon Press; Oxford University Press, New York, 1979. Pp. ix, 292. $29.00. One of the major disputes between natural law theorists and. legal positivists concerns the relationship between law and moral- ity.

  17. 8 Law and Morality: Essays in Applied Ethics

    Law arises in history, to all intents and purposes, side by side with other phenomena of the common life of humanity, such as language, religion, art, and so forth. 1 Close All these modes of the human spirit's life and action, without which man, as such, is inconceivable, cannot be simply products of reflection. Obviously, they cannot have their historical origin in the conscious and willful ...

  18. The Concept, the Idea, and The Morality of Law an Essay in

    This may be the case in Austria and the U.S.A. On the other hand LAW conceived in terms of morality can find no place for a positivist or morally neutral LAW-IDEA. For in this case an immoral "law" would be not merely, as in the former case, invalid within the system, but a contradiction in terms throughout the writer's Jurisprudence.

  19. Relationship Between Morality and the Law

    This essay will look at the issue of the relationship between morality and the law. The emotive topic will then be illustrated by looking at whether voluntary euthanasia should be legalised in England. The arguments for and against euthanasia are examined against a background of the various moral theories which clutter the topic.

  20. The Relation Between Law and Morality

    The problem of law and morality is rather difficult, as many believe that there are no explicit distinctions between them. There are cases when morals coincide with true legal laws since humans created them. The human reason here could subconsciously shape the morality of law. However, the existence of unjust laws proves that morality and ...

  21. Morality, Law and Conflicting Reasons for Action

    In The Concept of Law, H.L.A. Hart suggested that four formal features of morality distinguish it from law: importance, immunity from deliberate change, the nature of moral offences and the form of moral pressure. On closer examination, none of these supposed features clearly distinguishes morality from law, at least in the broad sense of ...

  22. Law and Morality Essay

    Some would identify law and morality, claiming that moral rules, as the ancient reflections of social values and personal beliefs, are potential law, enforced by the individual choice of moral duty. However, the moral standards are diverse, especially in multicultural societies; hence, a myriad of moral standards might not be generally ...

  23. An Open Letter to Law Students on the Death Penalty

    Abstract. This open letter to law students discusses the Model Penal Code's retraction of its provisions on death penalty procedure, with an emphasis on moral implications that are relevant to all future members of the bar.

  24. Authority, Law, and Morality

    His essays on 'Bentham and the Demystification of the Law' and on 'The Nightmare and the Noble Dream' 2 showed him to be consciously sharing the Benthamite sense of the excessive veneration in which the law is held in common-law countries, and its deleterious moral consequences. His fear that in recent years legal theory has lurched ...

  25. New York Times editorial board calls Donald Trump 'unfit to lead'

    In the piece, the editorial board outlined five "essential" qualities and values that they feel a president must have - and that they say Trump fails on: moral fitness, principled leadership ...