Untitled (Portrait of a Man and a Woman) (1851), daguerreotype, United States. Courtesy the Art Institute of Chicago
Tainted love
Love is both a wonderful thing and a cunning evolutionary trick to control us. a dangerous cocktail in the wrong hands.
by Anna Machin + BIO
We can all agree that, on balance, and taking everything into account, love is a wonderful thing. For many, it is the point of life. I have spent more than a decade researching the science behind human love and, rather than becoming immune to its charms, I am increasingly in awe of its complexity and its importance to us. It infiltrates every fibre of our being and every aspect of our daily lives. It is the most important factor in our mental and physical health, our longevity and our life satisfaction. And regardless of who the object of our love is – lover or friend, dog or god – these effects are largely underpinned, in the first instance, by the set of addictive neurochemicals supporting the bonds we create: oxytocin, dopamine, beta-endorphin and serotonin.
This suite of chemicals makes us feel euphoric and calm, they draw us towards those we love, and reward us for investing in our relationships, even when the going gets tough. Love feels wonderful but ultimately it is a form of biological bribery, a cunning evolutionary trick to make sure we cooperate and those all-important genes continue down the generations. The joy it brings is wonderful but is merely a side-effect. Its goal is to ensure our survival, and for this reason happiness is not always its end point. Alongside its joys, there exists a dark side.
Love is ultimately about control. It’s about using chemical bribery to make sure we stick around, cooperate and invest in each other, and particularly in the survival-critical relationships we have with our lovers, children and close friends. This is an evolutionary control of which we are hardly aware, and it brings many positive benefits.
But the addictive nature of these chemicals, and our visceral need for them, means that love also has a dark side. It can be used as a tool of exploitation, manipulation and abuse. Indeed, in part what may separate human love from the love experienced by other animals is that we can use love to manipulate and control others. Our desire to believe in the fairy tale means we rarely acknowledge the undercurrents but, as a scholar of love, I would be negligent if I did not consider it. Arguably our greatest and most intense life experience can be used against us, sometimes leading us to continue relationships with negative consequences in direct opposition to our survival.
We are all experts in love. The science I write about is always grounded in the lived experience of my subjects whose thoughts I collect as keenly as their empirical data. It might be the voice of the new father as he describes holding his firstborn, or the Catholic nun explaining how she works to maintain her relationship with God, or the aromantic detailing what it’s like living in a world apparently obsessed with the romantic love that they do not feel. I begin every interview in the same way, by asking what they think love is. Their answers are often surprising, always illuminating and invariably positive, and remind me that not all the answers to what love is can be found on the scanner screen or in the lab. But I will also ask them to consider whether love can ever be negative. The vast majority say no for, if love has a darker side, it is not love, and this is an interesting point to contemplate. But if they do acknowledge the possibility of love having a less sunny side, their go-to example is jealousy.
J ealousy is an emotion and, as with all emotions, it evolved to protect us, to alert us to a potential benefit or threat. It works its magic at three levels: the emotional, the cognitive and the behavioural. Physiology also throws its hat into the ring making you feel nauseous, faint or flushed. When we feel jealousy , it is generally urging us to do one of three things: to cut off the rival, to prevent our partner’s defection by redoubling our efforts, or to cut our losses and leave the relationship. All have evolved to make sure we balance the costs and benefits of the relationship. Investing time, energy and reproductive effort in the wrong partner is seriously damaging to your reproductive legacy and chances of survival. But what do we perceive to be a jealousy-inducing threat? The answer very much depends on your gender.
Men and women experience jealousy with the same intensity. However, there is a stark difference when it comes to what causes each to be jealous. One of the pioneers of human mating research is the American evolutionary psychologist David Buss and, in his book The Evolution of Desire (1994), he details numerous experiments that have highlighted this gender difference. In one study, in which subjects were asked to read different scenarios detailing incidences of sexual and emotional infidelity, 83 per cent of women found the emotional scenario the most jealousy-inducing, whereas only 40 per cent of men found this to be of concern. In contrast, 60 per cent of men found sexual infidelity difficult to deal with, compared with a significantly smaller percentage of women: 17 per cent.
Men also feel a much more extreme physiological response to sexual infidelity than women do. Hooking them up to monitors that measure skin conductance, muscle contraction and heartrate shows that men experience significant increases in heartrate, sweating and frowning when confronted with sexual infidelity, but the monitor readouts hardly flicker if their partner has become emotionally involved with a rival.
The reason for this difference sits with the different resources that men and women bring to the mating game. Broadly, men bring their resources and protection; women bring their womb. If a woman is sexually unfaithful and becomes pregnant with another man’s child, she has withdrawn the opportunity from her partner to father a child with her for at least nine months. Hence, he is the most concerned about sexual infidelity. In contrast, women are more concerned about emotional infidelity because this suggests that, if their partner does make a rival pregnant and becomes emotionally involved with her, his partner risks having to share his protection and resources with another, meaning that her children receive less of the pie.
To understand someone’s emotional needs means you can use that intelligence to control them
Jealousy is an evolved response to threats to our reproductive success and survival – of self, children and genes. In many cases, it is of positive benefit to those who experience it as it shines a light on the threat and enables us to decide what is best. But in some cases, jealousy gets out of hand.
Emotional intelligence sits at the core of healthy relationships. To truly deliver the benefits of the relationship to our partner, we must understand and meet their emotional needs as they must understand and meet ours. But, as with love, this skill has a darker side because to understand someone’s emotional needs presents the possibility that you can use that intelligence to control them. While we may all admit to using this skill for the wrong reasons every now and again – perhaps to get that sofa we desire or the holiday destination we prefer – for some, it is their go-to mechanism where relationships are concerned.
The most adept proponents of this skill are those who possess the Dark Triad of personality traits: Machiavellianism , psychopathy and narcissism . The first relies on using emotional intelligence to manipulate others, the second to toy with other’s feelings, and the third to denigrate others with the aim of glorifying oneself. For these people, characterised by exploitative, manipulative and callous personalities, emotional intelligence is the route to a set of mate-retention behaviours that certainly meet their goals but are less than beneficial to those whom they profess to love. Indeed, research has shown that a relationship with such a person leaves you open to a significantly greater risk that your love will be returned with abuse.
In 2018, the psychologist Razieh Chegeni and her team set out to explore whether a link existed between the Dark Triad and relationship abuse. Participants were identified as having the Dark Triad personality by expressing their degree of agreement with statements such as ‘I tend to want others to admire me’ (narcissism), ‘I tend to be unconcerned with the morality of my actions’ (psychopathy) and ‘I tend to exploit others to my own end’ (Machiavellianism). They then had to indicate to what extent they used a range of mate-retention behaviours, including ‘snooped through my partner’s personal belongings’, ‘talked to another man/woman at a party to make my partner jealous’, ‘bought my partner an expensive gift’ and ‘slapped a man who made a pass at my partner’.
The results were clear. Having a Dark Triad personality, whether you were a man or a woman, significantly increased the likelihood that ‘cost-inflicting mate-retention behaviours’ were your go-to mechanism when trying to retain your partner. These are behaviours that level an emotional, physical, practical and/or psychological cost on the partner such as physical or emotional abuse, coercive control or controlling access to food or money. Interestingly, however, these individuals did not employ this tactic all the time. There was nuance in their behaviour. Costly behaviours were peppered with rare incidences of gift giving or caretaking, so-called beneficial mate-retention behaviours. Why? Because the unpredictability of their behaviour caused psychological destabilisation in their partner and enabled them to assert further control through a practice we now identify as gaslighting .
The question remains – if these people are so destructive, why does their personality type persist in our population? Because, while their behaviour may harm those who are unfortunate enough to be close to them, they themselves must gain some survival advantage, which means that their traits persist in the population. It is true that no trait can be said to be 100 per cent beneficial, and here is a perfect example of where evolution is truly working at cross purposes.
N ot all Dark Triad personalities are abusers but the presence of abuse within our closest relationships is a very real phenomenon, the understanding of which continues to evolve and grow. Whereas we might have once imagined an abuser as someone who controlled their partner with their fists, we are now aware that abuse comes in many guises including emotional, psychological, reproductive and financial.
The US Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC) questioned both men and women in the United States about the incidences of domestic violence they had experienced in their lifetime. Looking at severe physical abuse alone – which means being punched, slammed, kicked, burned, choked, beaten or attacked with a weapon – one in five women and one in seven men reported at least one incidence in their lifetime. If we consider emotional abuse, then the statistics for men and women are closer – more than 43 million women and 38 million men have experienced psychological aggression by an intimate partner in their lifetime.
It is hard to imagine that, having experienced such a litany of abuse, anyone could believe that love remained within their relationship. But here the power of the lived experience, of allowing everyone to have their ideas about love becomes clearer. Because, while we have many scientific tools to explore love objectively, at the end of the day, there is always an element of our experience of love that is subjective, that another cannot touch. This is no more powerfully evidenced than by the testimony of those who have experienced intimate partner violence. In 2013, three mental health nurses, led by Marilyn Smith in West Virginia, explored what love meant to 19 women who were experiencing, or had experienced, intimate partner violence. For them, this kind of abuse included, but was not limited to, ‘slapping, intimidation, shaming, forced intercourse, isolation, monitoring behaviours, restricting access to healthcare, opposing or interfering with school or employment, and making decisions concerning contraception, pregnancy, and elective abortion’.
Our cultural ideas of romantic love have a role to play in trapping women in abusive relationships
It was clear from the transcripts that all the women knew what love wasn’t: being hurt and fearful, being controlled and having a lack of trust and a lack of support or concern for their welfare. And it was clear that they all knew what love should be: built on a foundation of respect and understanding, of support and encouragement, of commitment, loyalty and trust. But despite this clear understanding of the stark difference between the ideal and their reality, many of these women still believed that love existed within their relationship. Some hoped the power of their love would change the behaviour of their partner, others said their sense of attachment made them stay. Some feared losing love, however flawed; and, if they left, might they not land in a relationship where their treatment was even worse? A lot of the time, cultural messaging had reinforced strongly held beliefs about the supremacy of the nuclear family, making victims reluctant to leave in case they ultimately harmed their children’s life chances. While it can be hard to understand these arguments – surely a non-nuclear setup is preferable to the harm inflicted on a child by the observation of intimate partner abuse – I strongly believe that this population has as much right to their definition and experience of love as any of us.
In fact, the cultural messages we hear about romantic love – from the media, religion, parents and family – not only potentially trap us in ‘ideal’ family units: they may also play a role in our susceptibility to experiencing intimate partner abuse. This view of reproductive love, once confined to Western culture, is now the predominant narrative globally. From a young age, we speak of ‘the one’, we consume stories of young people finding love against all the odds, of sacrifice, of being consumed. It is arguable that these narratives are unhelpful generally as the reality, while wonderful, is considerably more complex, involving light and shade. But research has shown that these stories may have more significant consequences when we consider their role in intimate partner abuse.
South Africa has one of the highest rates of partner abuse against women in the world. In their 2017 paper , Shakila Singh and Thembeka Myende explored the role of resilience in female students at risk of abuse, which is prevalent at a high rate on South African university campuses. Their paper ranges widely over the role of resilience in resisting and surviving partner abuse, but what is of interest to me is the 15 women’s ideas about how our cultural ideas of romantic love have a role to play in trapping women in abusive relationships. These women’s arguments are powerful and made me rethink the fairy-tale. Singh and Myende point to the romantic idea that love overcomes all obstacles and must be maintained at all costs, even when abuse makes these costs life-threateningly high. Or the idea that love is about losing control, being swept off your feet, having no say in who you fall for, even if they turn out to be an abuser. Or that lovers protect each other, fight for each other to the end, even if the person who is being protected, usually from the authorities, is violent or coercive. Or the belief that love is blind and we are incapable of seeing our partner’s faults, despite them often being glaringly obvious to anyone outside the relationship.
It is these cultural ideas about romantic love, the women argue, that lead to the erosion of a woman’s power to leave or entirely avoid an abusive partner. Add these ideas to the powerful physiological and psychological need we have for love, and you leave an open goal for the abuser.
L ove is the focus of so much science, philosophy and literary rumination because we struggle to define it, to predict its next move. Thanks to our biology and the reproductive mandate of evolution, love has long controlled us. But what if we could control love?
What if a magic potion existed that could induce us, or another, to fall in love or even wipe away the memories of a failed relationship? It is a quest as ancient as the first writings 5,000 years ago and the focus of many literary endeavours, including Shakespeare’s A Midsummer Night’s Dream – who can forget Titania’s love for the ass-headed Bottom – and Wagner’s opera Tristan and Isolde . Even in a world where science has largely usurped magic, type ‘love potions’ into Google and the first two questions are: ‘How do you make a love potion?’ and ‘Do love potions actually work?’
But today we know enough about the chemistry of love for the elixir to be within our grasp. And we don’t have to look very far for our first candidate: synthetic oxytocin, used right now as an induction drug in labour. We know from extensive research in social neuroscience that artificial oxytocin also increases prosociality, trust and cooperation. Squirt it up the nose of new parents and it increases positive parenting behaviours. Oxytocin, as released by the brain when we are attracted to someone, is vital for the first stages of love because it quiets the fear centre of your brain and lowers your inhibitions to forming new relationships. Would a squirt up the nose do the same before you head out on a Saturday night?
The other possibility is MDMA or ecstasy, which mimics the neurochemical of long-term love, beta-endorphin. Recreational users of ecstasy report that it makes them feel boundless love for their fellow clubbers and increases their empathy. Researchers in the US have reported encouraging results when MDMA was used in marriage therapy to increase empathy, allowing participants to gain further insight into each other’s needs and find common ground.
Love drugs could end up being yet another form of abuse
Both of these sound like promising candidates but there are still issues to iron out and ethical discussions to have. How effective they are is highly context dependent. Based on their genetics , some people do exactly what is predicted of them. Boundaries are lowered and love sensations abound. But for a significant minority, particularly when it comes to oxytocin, people do exactly the opposite of what we would expect. For some, a dose of oxytocin, while increasing bonds with those they perceive to be in their in-group, increases feelings of ethnocentrism – racism – toward the out-group.
MDMA has other issues . For some people, it simply does not work. But the bigger problem is that the effects endure only while usage continues; anecdotal evidence suggests that, if you stop, the feelings of love and empathy disappear. This raises questions of practicality and ethical issues surrounding power imbalance. If you commenced a relationship while taking MDMA, would you have to continue? What if you were in a relationship with someone who had taken MDMA and you didn’t know? What would happen if they stopped? And could someone be induced to take MDMA against their will?
The ethical conversation around love drugs is complex. On one side are those who argue that taking a love drug is no more controversial than an antidepressant. Both alter your brain chemistry and, given the strong relationship between love and good mental and physical health, surely it is important that we use all the tools at our disposal to help people succeed? But maybe an anecdote from the book Love Is the Drug (2020) by Brian Earp and Julian Savulescu will give you pause. They describe SSRI prescriptions used to suppress the sexual urges of young male yeshiva students, to ensure that they comply with Jewish orthodox religious law – no sex before marriage, and definitely no homosexuality.
Could such drugs gain wider traction in repressive regimes as a weapon against what some perceive to be immoral forms of love? Remember that 71 countries still deem homosexuality to be illegal. It is not a massive leap of imagination to envisage the use of SSRIs to ‘cure’ people of this ‘affliction’. We only have to look at the continued existence of conversion therapy to see that this is a distinct possibility. Love drugs could end up being yet another form of abuse over which the individual has very little control.
Evolution saw fit to give us love to ensure we would continue to form and maintain the cooperative relationships that are our route to personal and, most crucially, genetic survival. It can be the source of euphoric happiness, calm contentment and much-needed security, but this is not its point. Love is merely the sweet treat handed to you by your babysitter to make sure the goal is achieved. Combine the ultimate evolutionary aim of love with our visceral need for it and the quick intelligence of our brains, and you have the recipe for a darker side to emerge. Some of this darker side is adaptive but, for those who experience it, it rarely ends well. At the very least there is pain – physical, psychological, financial – and, at the most, there is death, and the grief of those we leave behind.
Maybe it is time to rewrite the stories we tell ourselves about love because the danger on the horizon is not the dragon that needs to be slain by the knight to save the beautiful princess but the presence of some who mean to use its powers for their gain and our considerable loss. Like all of us, love is a complex beast: only by embracing it in its entirety do we truly understand it, and ourselves. And this means understanding its evolutionary story, the good and the bad.
Metaphysics
Many worlds, many selves
If it’s true that we live in a vast multiverse, then our understanding of identity, morality and even God must be reexamined
Emily Qureshi-Hurst
Biography and memoir
A grief with no name
As a child, I was torn from a culture that I never knew. It is a loss that defines me, even as I struggle to define the loss
Jelena Markovic
Could humans hibernate?
Hibernation allows many animals to time-travel from difficult times to plenty. Could humans learn how to do it too?
Vladyslav Vyazovskiy
The cochlear question
As the hearing parent of a deaf baby, I’m confronted with an agonising decision: should I give her an implant to help her hear?
Abi Stephenson
Philosophy of science
The nature of natural laws
Physicists and philosophers today have formulated three opposing models that explain how laws work. Which is the best?
Mario Hubert
Technology and the self
We need raw awe
In this tech-vexed age, our life on screens prevents us from experiencing the mysteries and transformative wonder of life
Kirk Schneider
- Relationships
10 Reasons Why Romantic Love Can Be So Dangerous
Part 1: regardless of your age, romantic love activates your inner adolescent..
Posted August 11, 2021 | Reviewed by Lybi Ma
- Why Relationships Matter
- Take our Relationship Satisfaction Test
- Find counselling to strengthen relationships
- Love should involve emotion and reason; but regrettably, your rational faculties can be swept away by powerful amorous feelings.
- By too readily trusting your beloved, should the relationship end badly, placing so much confidence in them can come back to haunt you.
- Distracted by the thrilling “high” of courtship, women may give up or postpone their pre-romantic plans, which they may later regret.
- If you marry your beloved, you’ll soon realize they were never as “special” as—in your dreamy-eyed “love-sightedness”—you believed they were.
Romantic love is typically the most exciting experience you’ll ever have. What could be more thrilling, more gratifying, or (in endorphin production) more chemically rewarding? Still, many dangers link to this love. It frequently culminates in disappointment, hurt, regret, or—at its worst—despair. Here are 10 examples of its negative potential:
1. By altering your consciousness, love can lead you to feel, and act, off-balance. The descriptive phrases “ falling in love” or “ head over heels in love” testify to how easily this euphoric state can “trip you up.” It can make you behave “lopsidedly” to situations that realistically hardly warrant such a reaction.
The expression, “love is blind,” additionally alludes to not being able to see straight, indicating a myopic vision prompting you to ignore details that could be crucial.
2. When powerful feelings about your beloved not only dim your clear-sightedness but also what your friends and relatives may be telling you, the chances of making a beguiled mistake increase further. Others may be much more aware of critical warning signs that, amorously (or stubbornly) viewing your partner through a heavily biased, favorable filter, cause you to discount or dismiss their concerns.
3. There’s a strangely involuntary, uncontrollable aspect to romantic love. With a diminished ability to think logically about what’s happening to you, you may not be able to grasp the irrational dynamics of your inordinate passion. And regrettably, this emotionally or lustfully charged attraction might well oppose your (no-longer-accessible) better judgment and not at all reflect your basic values.
4. It could be that when you speak to, or even think about, the person you’re in love with, you feel tense, uneasy, and nervous—even when there’s no one on earth you’d rather be with. And, however ironic, it’s well known that “highs” can produce as much stress as “lows.”
5. Your ability to think lucidly is compromised when you’re full of romantic feelings. Ideally, love should involve emotion and reason, the two coming together in a manner that makes rational sense. But your rational faculties can be swept away when amorous feelings take you over.
6. It can threaten, or undermine, your integrity. If your self-acceptance is limited, inflicted with notions (real or not) of not being good enough, you’ll hide from your partner whatever qualities you associate with personal weakness or inadequacy. Unwilling to risk criticism or rejection, you’ll edit your behavior accordingly, only letting yourself be known to the degree it feels relationally safe.
But risk-reducing stratagems can’t be maintained indefinitely. If the relationship becomes longer-term, your actual (vs. imagined) deficits will become increasingly evident, jeopardizing the relationship.
7. Trusting someone is never without danger. In romantic love, when you’re over -confident about your partner’s unconditional acceptance, you’ll likely bare your soul to them, taking risks you probably wouldn’t take with anybody else. By all-too-readily extending such trust, should the relationship end badly your prematurely placing so much confidence in them can come back to haunt you.
8. Closely related to the above is that if the relationship is cut short, you’ll likely become more cynical. And although this increased skepticism may protect you from dashing headlong into another misguided relationship, researchers have connected a suspicious attitude to a shorter lifespan, and less happiness generally. Furthermore, because trusting others represents a fundamental human need, what you presumably learned from your intensely painful disillusionment can make it much harder to trust a prospective mate going forward.
9. In a romantic relationship , it’s normal to become preoccupied with your love object. Your hopes, dreams , and fears can be so absorbing that you may not be able to adequately attend to other responsibilities and commitments—like your studies, vocation, and other important relationships and pursuits. But disregarding what remains key to your personal and professional welfare is perilous, it can lead you to fail a course, get fired from your job, and so on.
It cannot be emphasized enough that romantic interests ought to be balanced by (non- narcissistic ) self-interests. Nonetheless, that can be a real challenge if you’re not sufficiently secure about being the other’s equal.
10. As pertains specifically to single women, Bella DePaulo, referring to several studies on the subject, reports that the career aspirations of many women end up taking a backseat to an all-consuming romantic relationship. Seduced by the extraordinary high experienced during courtship, they may give up or postpone pre-romantic plans. And later they may come to regret the "all for love" mentality that so distracted them from what earlier had been their foremost priority.
Doubtless, from your own experience of being in love you can think of more reasons to be cautious about its consequent thoughts and feelings, which can negatively affect your better judgment. My next post will list an additional 10 reasons. But right now you might want to add to the present list, to see how many of them dovetail with my upcoming post.
© 2021 Leon F. Seltzer, Ph.D. All Rights Reserved.
Capulet, S. (2019, Feb 11). Why We’re Obsessed With Romantic Love and Why It’s Dangerous. https://thoughtcatalog.com/sarah-capulet/2019/02/why-were-obsessed-with…
DePaulo, B. ( 2018, Nov 7). In Love With Romantic Love? That Comes With Risks. https://www.psychologytoday.com/us/blog/living-single/201811/in-love-ro…
Foy, K. (2017, Oct 6), 6 Things That Seem Really Romantic in Your Relationship, But Are Actually Dangerous. https://www.alliant.edu/blog/dangerous-disease-love
How Romanticism Ruined Love (n.a. & n.d.) https://www.theschooloflife.com/thebookoflife/how-romanticism-ruined-lo…
Langrial, D. (2020, Nov 6). Being Romantic Is the Most Dangerous Thing a Man or Woman Can Do. https://medium.com/illumination/being-romantic-is-the-most-dangerous-th…
Raypole, C. (2020, Aug 5). 15 Ways Love Affects Your Brain and Body. https://www.healthline.com/health/relationships/effects-of-love
Seltzer, L. F. (2013, Jun 21). How Rational Are “Rational” Marriages? https://www.psychologytoday.com/us/blog/evolution-the-self/201306/how-r…
Seltzer, L. F. (2017, Sept 1). 15 Reasons to Be Wary About Falling in Love. https://www.psychologytoday.com/us/blog/evolution-the-self/201709/15-re…
Seltzer, L. F. (2021, Aug 12). 10 More Reasons Why Romantic Love Can Be So Dangerous. https://www.psychologytoday.com/us/node/1165305/preview
Shorr, L. (2021, Apr 20). It Must Be Love on the Brain: The Neuroscience of Love. http://www.stitchfashion.com/home//love-on-the-brain
Villasenor, C. (n.d.). The Dangerous Disease that is Love. https://www.alliant.edu/blog/dangerous-disease-love
Leon F. Seltzer, Ph.D. , is the author of Paradoxical Strategies in Psychotherapy and The Vision of Melville and Conrad . He holds doctorates in English and Psychology. As of mid-July 2024, Dr. Seltzer has published some 590 posts, which have received over 54 million views.
- Find Counselling
- Find a Support Group
- Find Online Therapy
- United Kingdom
- Asperger's
- Bipolar Disorder
- Chronic Pain
- Eating Disorders
- Passive Aggression
- Personality
- Goal Setting
- Positive Psychology
- Stopping Smoking
- Low Sexual Desire
- Child Development
- Self Tests NEW
- Therapy Center
- Diagnosis Dictionary
- Types of Therapy
When we fall prey to perfectionism, we think we’re honorably aspiring to be our very best, but often we’re really just setting ourselves up for failure, as perfection is impossible and its pursuit inevitably backfires.
- Emotional Intelligence
- Gaslighting
- Affective Forecasting
- Neuroscience
- Ask LitCharts AI
- Discussion Question Generator
- Essay Prompt Generator
- Quiz Question Generator
- Literature Guides
- Poetry Guides
- Shakespeare Translations
- Literary Terms
Romeo and Juliet
William shakespeare.
“These violent delights have violent ends,” says Friar Laurence in an attempt to warn Romeo , early on in the play, of the dangers of falling in love too hard or too fast. In the world of Romeo and Juliet , love is not pretty or idealized—it is chaotic and dangerous. Throughout the play, love is connected through word and action with violence, and Romeo and Juliet ’s deepest mutual expression of love occurs when the “star-crossed lovers take their life.” By connecting love with pain and ultimately with suicide, Shakespeare suggests that there is an inherent sense of violence in many of the physical and emotional facets of expressing love—a chaotic and complex emotion very different from the serene, idealized sweetness it’s so often portrayed as being.
There are countless instances throughout Romeo and Juliet in which love and violence are connected. After their marriage, Juliet imagines in detail the passion she and Romeo will share on their wedding night, and invokes the Elizabethan characterization of orgasm as a small death or “petite mort”—she looks forward to the moment she will “die” and see Romeo’s face reflected in the stars above her. When Romeo overhears Juliet say that she wishes he were not a Montague so that they could be together, he declares that his name is “hateful” and offers to write it down on a piece of paper just so he can rip it up and obliterate it—and, along with it, his very identity, and sense of self as part of the Montague family. When Juliet finds out that her parents, ignorant of her secret marriage to Romeo, have arranged for her to marry Paris , she goes to Friar Laurence’s chambers with a knife, threatening to kill herself if he is unable to come up with a plan that will allow her to escape her second marriage. All of these examples represent just a fraction of the instances in which language and action conspire to render love as a “violent delight” whose “violent ends” result in danger, injury, and even death. Feeling oneself in the throes of love, Shakespeare suggests, is tumultuous and destabilizing enough—but the real violence of love, he argues, emerges in the many ways of expressing love.
Emotional and verbal expressions of love are the ones most frequently deployed throughout the play. Romeo and Juliet wax poetic about their great love for each other—and the misery they feel as a result of that love—over and over again, and at great lengths. Often, one of their friends or servants must cut them off mid-speech—otherwise, Shakespeare seems to suggest, Romeo and Juliet would spend hours trying to wrestle their feelings into words. Though Romeo and Juliet say lovely things about one another, to be sure, their speeches about each other, or about love more broadly, are almost always tinged with violence, which illustrates their chaotic passion for each other and their desire to mow down anything that stands in its way. When Romeo, for instance, spots Juliet at her window in the famous “balcony scene” in Act 2, Scene 2, he wills her to come closer by whispering, “Arise, fair sun ”—a beautiful metaphor of his love and desire for Juliet—and quickly follows his entreaty with the dangerous language “and kill the envious moon, Who is already sick and pale with grief.” Juliet’s “sun”-like radiance makes Romeo want her to “kill” the moon (or Rosaline ,) his former love and her rival in beauty and glory, so that Juliet can reign supreme over his heart. Later on in the play, when the arrival of dawn brings an end to Romeo and Juliet’s first night together as man and wife, Juliet invokes the symbol of a lark’s song—traditionally a symbol of love and sweetness—as a violent, ill-meaning presence which seeks to pull Romeo and Juliet apart, “arm from arm,” and “hunt” Romeo out of Juliet’s chambers. Romeo calls love a “rough” thing which “pricks” him like a thorn; Juliet says that if she could love and possess Romeo in the way she wants to, as if he were her pet bird, she would “kill [him] with much cherishing.” The way the two young lovers at the heart of the play speak about love shows an enormously violent undercurrent to their emotions—as they attempt to name their feelings and express themselves, they resort to violence-tinged speech to convey the enormity of their emotions.
Physical expressions of love throughout the play also carry violent connotations. From Romeo and Juliet’s first kiss, described by each of them as a “sin” and a “trespass,” to their last, in which Juliet seeks to kill herself by sucking remnants of poison from the dead Romeo’s lips, the way Romeo and Juliet conceive of the physical and sexual aspects of love are inextricable from how they conceive of violence. Juliet looks forward to “dying” in Romeo’s arms—again, one Elizabethan meaning of the phrase “to die” is to orgasm—while Romeo, just after drinking a vial of poison so lethal a few drops could kill 20 men, chooses to kiss Juliet as his dying act. The violence associated with these acts of sensuality and physical touch furthers Shakespeare’s argument that attempts to adequately express the chaotic, overwhelming, and confusing feelings of intense passion often lead to a commingling with violence.
Violent expressions of love are at the heart of Romeo and Juliet . In presenting and interrogating them, Shakespeare shows his audiences—in the Elizabethan area, the present day, and the centuries in-between—that love is not pleasant, reserved, cordial, or sweet. Rather, it is a violent and all-consuming force. As lovers especially those facing obstacles and uncertainties like the ones Romeo and Juliet encounter, struggle to express their love, there may be eruptions of violence both between the lovers themselves and within the communities of which they’re a part.
Love and Violence ThemeTracker
Love and Violence Quotes in Romeo and Juliet
Two households, both alike in dignity, In fair Verona, where we lay our scene, From ancient grudge break to new mutiny, Where civil blood makes civil hands unclean. From forth the fatal loins of these two foes, A pair of star-cross'd lovers take their life; Whose misadventured piteous overthrows, Doth with their death bury their parents' strife. The fearful passage of their death-mark'd love, And the continuance of their parents' rage, Which, but their children's end, nought could remove, Is now the two hours' traffic of our stage; The which if you with patient ears attend, What here shall miss, our toil shall strive to mend.
Why then, O brawling love! O loving hate! O any thing, of nothing first created; O heavy lightness! serious vanity! Mis-shapen chaos of well-seeming forms!
Oh, she doth teach the torches to burn bright! It seems she hangs upon the cheek of night Like a rich jewel in an Ethiope's ear, Beauty too rich for use, for earth too dear. So shows a snowy dove trooping with crows As yonder lady o'er her fellows shows. The measure done, I'll watch her place of stand, And, touching hers, make blessèd my rude hand. Did my heart love till now? Forswear it, sight! For I ne'er saw true beauty till this night.
You kiss by th’ book.
My only love sprung from my only hate! Too early seen unknown, and known too late!
But, soft! what light through yonder window breaks? It is the east, and Juliet is the sun!
O Romeo, Romeo! wherefore art thou Romeo? Deny thy father and refuse thy name; Or, if thou wilt not, be but sworn my love, And I'll no longer be a Capulet.
'Tis but thy name that is my enemy; — Thou art thyself though, not a Montague. What's Montague? It is nor hand, nor foot, Nor arm, nor face, nor any other part Belonging to a man. O, be some other name! What's in a name? That which we call a rose, By any other word would smell as sweet; So Romeo would, were he not Romeo call'd, Retain that dear perfection which he owes Without that title: — Romeo, doff thy name; And for thy name, which is no part of thee, Take all myself.
I take thee at thy word: Call me but love, and I'll be new baptis'd; Henceforth I never will be Romeo.
O, swear not by the moon, the inconstant moon, That monthly changes in her circled orb, Lest that thy love prove likewise variable.
Good-night, good-night! Parting is such sweet sorrow That I shall say good-night till it be morrow.
Romeo, the hate I bear thee can afford No better term than this: thou art a villain.
Romeo: Courage, man; the hurt cannot be much. Mercutio: No, 'tis not so deep as a well, nor so wide as a church-door; but 'tis enough, 'twill serve: ask for me to-morrow, and you shall find me a grave man.
O, I am fortune's fool!
Come, gentle night, — come, loving black brow'd night, Give me my Romeo; and when he shall die, Take him and cut him out in little stars, And he will make the face of Heaven so fine That all the world will be in love with night, And pay no worship to the garish sun.
Wilt thou be gone? it is not yet near day. It was the nightingale, and not the lark, That pierc'd the fearful hollow of thine ear; Nightly she sings on yond pomegranate tree. Believe me love, it was the nightingale.
Is there no pity sitting in the clouds That sees into the bottom of my grief? O sweet my mother, cast me not away! Delay this marriage for a month, a week, Or if you do not, make the bridal bed In that dim monument where Tybalt lies.
Or bid me go into a new-made grave, And hide me with a dead man in his shroud - Things that, to hear them told, have made me tremble - And I will do it without fear or doubt, To live an unstain'd wife to my sweet love.
Then I defy you, stars!
O true apothecary! Thy drugs are quick. — Thus with a kiss I die.
Yea, noise, then I'll be brief; O, happy dagger! This is thy sheath; there rest, and let me die.
For never was a story of more woe Than this of Juliet and her Romeo.
- Quizzes, saving guides, requests, plus so much more.
Lit. Summaries
- Biographies
Exploring the Perils of Passion: A Review of Dangerous Love (1996) by Ben Okri
In his 1996 book Dangerous Love, Nigerian author Ben Okri delves into the complex and often perilous nature of love. Through a series of interconnected stories set in Lagos, Okri explores the ways in which love can bring both joy and pain, and how it can be both a source of liberation and a trap. This review will examine Okri’s portrayal of love in Dangerous Love, and consider the book’s wider themes and messages.
Themes of Dangerous Love
One of the central themes of Dangerous Love is the idea that love can be a dangerous and destructive force. The novel explores the ways in which love can lead people to make irrational decisions and engage in destructive behavior. This theme is exemplified in the character of Omovo, who becomes obsessed with his love for Ifeyi, a woman who is already married. Omovo’s obsession with Ifeyi leads him to engage in reckless behavior, including stealing and violence. The novel also explores the idea that love can be a source of power and control, as seen in the character of Ifeyi’s husband, Osifo, who uses his love for her as a means of exerting control over her. Overall, Dangerous Love offers a complex and nuanced exploration of the perils of passion, highlighting the ways in which love can both inspire and destroy.
Analysis of Characters
In Dangerous Love, Ben Okri presents a cast of characters whose passions lead them down dangerous paths. The protagonist, Omovo, is a young artist who becomes infatuated with a mysterious woman named Ifeyiwa. His obsession with her leads him to neglect his own art and become entangled in a web of deceit and violence. Ifeyiwa herself is a complex character, with a past shrouded in mystery and a present filled with secrets. The novel also features a cast of supporting characters, including Omovo’s friend Kola and Ifeyiwa’s husband, who add depth and complexity to the story. Through his portrayal of these characters, Okri explores the ways in which passion can both inspire and destroy, and the dangers of becoming too consumed by one’s desires.
Okri’s Writing Style
Okri’s writing style in Dangerous Love is both poetic and philosophical. He weaves together vivid imagery and introspective musings to create a hauntingly beautiful narrative. His use of language is masterful, with each sentence carefully crafted to convey a deeper meaning. Okri’s writing is not just about telling a story, but about exploring the human condition and the complexities of love. He delves into the darker aspects of passion, exposing the perils that come with it. Through his writing, Okri challenges readers to question their own beliefs about love and the sacrifices they are willing to make for it. Overall, Okri’s writing style in Dangerous Love is a testament to his skill as a writer and his ability to create a thought-provoking and emotionally resonant story.
The Role of Fate in the Novel
In Dangerous Love, Ben Okri explores the role of fate in the lives of his characters. The novel is set in Nigeria during the 1970s, a time of political upheaval and social change. The main characters, Omovo and Ifeyiwa, are young lovers who are caught up in the tumultuous events of their time. They are both passionate and idealistic, but their love is threatened by the forces of fate that seem to be working against them. Okri uses the theme of fate to explore the idea that our lives are not entirely within our control, and that we are often at the mercy of forces beyond our understanding. Through the experiences of Omovo and Ifeyiwa, Okri shows us how love can be both a source of joy and a source of pain, and how the choices we make can have far-reaching consequences. Ultimately, Dangerous Love is a powerful meditation on the human condition, and a testament to the enduring power of love in the face of adversity.
Exploring the Concept of Love
Love is a complex and multifaceted concept that has been explored in literature, art, and philosophy for centuries. It is a feeling that can bring immense joy and happiness, but it can also lead to heartbreak and pain. In his novel Dangerous Love, Ben Okri delves into the darker side of love and the perils that can come with it. The book tells the story of a young couple, Omovo and Ifeyiwa, who fall deeply in love but are faced with numerous obstacles that threaten to tear them apart. Through their struggles, Okri explores the idea that love can be both beautiful and dangerous, and that it is often difficult to navigate the complexities of human relationships. As readers follow Omovo and Ifeyiwa’s journey, they are forced to confront their own ideas about love and the risks that come with it. Ultimately, Dangerous Love is a powerful exploration of the human heart and the many ways in which it can be both a source of joy and a source of pain.
The Dangers of Obsession
Obsession can be a dangerous thing. It can consume a person’s thoughts and actions, leading them down a path of destruction. In his novel Dangerous Love, Ben Okri explores the perils of passion and the consequences of obsession. The characters in the novel are driven by their desires, and their actions have devastating consequences. Okri’s novel serves as a cautionary tale, warning readers of the dangers of obsession and the importance of self-control. Whether it be an obsession with a person, an idea, or a goal, it is important to maintain a healthy balance and not let our passions consume us. The characters in Dangerous Love learn this lesson the hard way, and their experiences serve as a reminder to us all to be mindful of our own obsessions.
Symbolism in Dangerous Love
Symbolism plays a significant role in Ben Okri’s Dangerous Love. The novel is filled with various symbols that add depth and meaning to the story. One of the most prominent symbols in the novel is the river. The river represents the flow of life and the journey that the characters must take. It is also a symbol of danger and uncertainty, as the characters must navigate through the treacherous waters to reach their destination. Another important symbol in the novel is the snake. The snake represents temptation and danger, as it is a creature that can be both beautiful and deadly. The snake is also a symbol of transformation, as it sheds its skin and emerges anew. These symbols, along with others in the novel, add layers of meaning to the story and help to create a rich and complex narrative.
Comparing Dangerous Love to Okri’s Other Works
When comparing Dangerous Love to Ben Okri’s other works, it becomes clear that the themes of love, passion, and the human condition are recurring motifs in his writing. However, what sets Dangerous Love apart is its focus on the dangers of love and how it can lead to destruction and chaos. This is a departure from Okri’s more mystical and magical works, such as The Famished Road and Songs of Enchantment, which explore the spiritual and supernatural realms.
In Dangerous Love, Okri delves into the complexities of human relationships and the consequences of giving in to our desires. The novel is set against the backdrop of political turmoil in Nigeria, and Okri uses this as a metaphor for the tumultuous nature of love. The characters are caught up in a web of passion, jealousy, and betrayal, and their actions have far-reaching consequences.
While Dangerous Love may not be as well-known as some of Okri’s other works, it is a powerful and thought-provoking novel that deserves more attention. It showcases Okri’s ability to explore the human psyche and the darker aspects of our nature, and it is a testament to his skill as a writer. Overall, Dangerous Love is a must-read for fans of Okri’s work and anyone interested in exploring the perils of passion.
Impact of the Setting on the Story
The setting of Dangerous Love plays a crucial role in shaping the story and its characters. The novel is set in Lagos, Nigeria, during a time of political and social upheaval. The city is portrayed as chaotic, dangerous, and unpredictable, with poverty and corruption rampant. This setting creates a sense of tension and unease throughout the novel, as the characters navigate their way through a world that is constantly changing and often hostile.
The setting also reflects the themes of the novel, particularly the dangers of passion and the consequences of obsession. Lagos is a city of extremes, where love and hate, hope and despair, are all heightened. The characters are driven by their desires, whether it be for power, money, or love, and the setting amplifies the intensity of these emotions.
Furthermore, the setting of Lagos is integral to the character development of the protagonist, Omovo. As a young artist, Omovo is drawn to the vibrant and chaotic city, but as he becomes more involved in the dangerous world of politics and corruption, he begins to see the darker side of Lagos. The city becomes a symbol of his own inner turmoil, as he struggles to reconcile his passion for art with his growing disillusionment with the world around him.
Overall, the setting of Dangerous Love is a powerful and evocative element of the novel, shaping the story and its characters in profound ways. It is a testament to Ben Okri’s skill as a writer that he is able to create such a vivid and compelling portrait of Lagos, and use it to explore complex themes of love, obsession, and the human condition.
The Use of Magical Realism in Dangerous Love
In Dangerous Love, Ben Okri employs the literary technique of magical realism to explore the complexities of love and its perils. Magical realism is a genre that blends the real and the fantastical, creating a world where the supernatural and the ordinary coexist. Okri uses this technique to create a dreamlike atmosphere that blurs the lines between reality and imagination. The novel is set in a fictional African city, where the characters are confronted with a series of surreal events that challenge their beliefs and perceptions. The use of magical realism allows Okri to delve into the psychological and emotional aspects of love, portraying it as a force that can both heal and destroy. The novel’s protagonist, Omovo, is a young artist who falls in love with an enigmatic woman named Ifeyiwa. Their relationship is fraught with danger and uncertainty, as they navigate the complexities of their feelings and the social and political turmoil of their city. Through the use of magical realism, Okri creates a world that is both familiar and strange, where the boundaries between love and madness are blurred. The novel’s ending is both tragic and hopeful, as Omovo comes to terms with the consequences of his actions and the power of love to transform and transcend. Overall, Dangerous Love is a powerful exploration of the human heart and its capacity for both beauty and destruction.
Exploring the Themes of Betrayal and Revenge
Betrayal and revenge are two themes that are intricately woven into the fabric of Dangerous Love by Ben Okri. The novel explores the consequences of betrayal and the lengths to which individuals will go to exact revenge. The characters in the novel are driven by their passions, which ultimately lead them down a path of destruction. The theme of betrayal is evident in the relationships between the characters, particularly in the love triangle between the protagonist, Omovo, his lover, Ifeyiwa, and her husband, Osifo. The betrayal of trust and loyalty leads to a series of events that ultimately result in tragedy. The theme of revenge is also prevalent in the novel, as the characters seek to avenge the wrongs that have been done to them. The desire for revenge consumes the characters, leading them to commit acts of violence and destruction. The novel serves as a cautionary tale about the dangers of passion and the destructive consequences of betrayal and revenge.
The Significance of Dreams in the Novel
In Dangerous Love, dreams play a significant role in the development of the story and the characters. The dreams are not just random occurrences, but rather they serve as a means of foreshadowing events and revealing the inner thoughts and emotions of the characters. The dreams are often surreal and symbolic, adding to the overall mystical and magical tone of the novel. Okri uses dreams to explore the themes of love, passion, and the dangers that come with them. The dreams also serve as a reminder that reality is not always what it seems and that there is a deeper, more profound meaning to life. Overall, the significance of dreams in Dangerous Love cannot be overstated, as they add depth and complexity to the story and the characters, making it a truly unforgettable read.
Analysis of the Ending
The ending of Dangerous Love by Ben Okri is both satisfying and thought-provoking. The main character, Omovo, finally realizes the destructive nature of his obsession with Ifeyiwa and decides to let her go. This decision is a significant turning point for Omovo, as he has spent the entire novel consumed by his desire for Ifeyiwa.
However, the ending also leaves the reader with questions about the future of Omovo and Ifeyiwa’s relationship. Will Omovo be able to move on from his obsession and find happiness? Will Ifeyiwa ever forgive him for his past behavior? These questions are left unanswered, leaving the reader to ponder the complexities of love and the consequences of obsession.
Overall, the ending of Dangerous Love is a fitting conclusion to a novel that explores the perils of passion. It highlights the importance of self-reflection and the dangers of allowing one’s desires to consume them.
The Role of Tradition in Dangerous Love
In Ben Okri’s Dangerous Love, tradition plays a significant role in shaping the characters’ actions and beliefs. The novel is set in Nigeria during the 1970s, a time when traditional values and customs were still deeply ingrained in society. The protagonist, Omovo, is torn between his love for Ifeyiwa, a woman from a wealthy family, and his loyalty to his own cultural traditions.
Ifeyiwa’s family disapproves of their relationship because Omovo is not of the same social status as them. They believe that Ifeyiwa should marry someone from a similar background, someone who can provide for her and maintain their family’s reputation. Omovo, on the other hand, is deeply in love with Ifeyiwa and is willing to go against tradition to be with her.
Throughout the novel, Okri explores the tension between tradition and modernity, and how it affects the characters’ relationships and identities. Omovo’s struggle to reconcile his love for Ifeyiwa with his loyalty to his cultural traditions is a reflection of the larger societal conflict between tradition and progress.
In Dangerous Love, tradition is portrayed as both a source of comfort and a hindrance to personal growth. While it provides a sense of belonging and continuity, it can also be oppressive and limiting. Okri’s novel highlights the importance of questioning tradition and challenging societal norms in order to achieve personal fulfillment and happiness.
Exploring the Themes of Power and Control
In Dangerous Love, Ben Okri explores the themes of power and control through the tumultuous relationship between the two main characters, Omovo and Ifeyiwa. Omovo, a young artist, becomes infatuated with Ifeyiwa, a mysterious and alluring woman who seems to hold a power over him that he cannot resist. As their relationship progresses, Ifeyiwa’s control over Omovo becomes more apparent, and he begins to lose himself in her world of secrets and manipulation.
Through this portrayal of a toxic relationship, Okri highlights the dangers of allowing someone else to have power and control over one’s life. He shows how easily one can become trapped in a cycle of abuse and manipulation, unable to break free from the hold that another person has over them.
Furthermore, Okri also explores the idea of power dynamics within society, particularly in relation to gender. Ifeyiwa’s power over Omovo is rooted in her femininity and sexuality, which she uses to manipulate and control him. This highlights the ways in which women are often objectified and reduced to their physical attributes, and how this can be used as a tool for power and control.
Overall, Dangerous Love is a powerful exploration of the themes of power and control, and the perils of allowing oneself to become trapped in a toxic relationship. Okri’s vivid and evocative writing brings these themes to life, and serves as a cautionary tale for anyone who may find themselves in a similar situation.
Comparing Dangerous Love to Other Works of African Literature
When comparing Dangerous Love to other works of African literature, it is clear that Ben Okri’s novel stands out for its unique blend of magical realism and social commentary. While many African writers have explored themes of love, betrayal, and political upheaval, few have done so with the same level of poetic language and surreal imagery as Okri.
One work that comes to mind when considering Dangerous Love is Chinua Achebe’s Things Fall Apart. Both novels deal with the clash between traditional African culture and the forces of colonialism, and both feature complex characters struggling to navigate their changing world. However, while Achebe’s novel is more straightforward in its narrative style, Okri’s prose is more dreamlike and symbolic, blurring the lines between reality and fantasy.
Another work that shares some similarities with Dangerous Love is Tsitsi Dangarembga’s Nervous Conditions. Like Okri’s novel, Dangarembga’s book explores the challenges faced by young people growing up in a rapidly changing society. However, while Nervous Conditions is primarily focused on issues of gender and education, Dangerous Love is more concerned with the nature of love itself, and the ways in which it can both inspire and destroy us.
Overall, while Dangerous Love may share some thematic similarities with other works of African literature, its unique style and perspective make it a standout novel in its own right. Okri’s poetic language and vivid imagery make for a captivating read, while his exploration of the dangers of passion and obsession is both thought-provoking and emotionally resonant.
Okri’s Views on Love and Relationships
In Dangerous Love, Ben Okri explores the complexities of love and relationships in a society that is plagued by political and social unrest. Okri’s views on love and relationships are deeply rooted in the African culture, where love is seen as a force that can bring people together or tear them apart. According to Okri, love is not just a feeling but a way of life that requires sacrifice, commitment, and understanding. He believes that love is a powerful force that can transform individuals and society as a whole. However, Okri also acknowledges the dangers of love, especially when it is driven by passion and desire. In his book, he portrays the perils of love through the experiences of his characters, who are often caught in a web of love and betrayal. Okri’s views on love and relationships are both insightful and thought-provoking, and they offer a unique perspective on the complexities of human emotions.
The Significance of the Title
The title of a book can often provide insight into the themes and messages that the author is trying to convey. In the case of Ben Okri’s Dangerous Love, the title is particularly significant as it encapsulates the central theme of the novel. The story explores the dangers that can arise when passion is allowed to run unchecked, and how this can lead to destructive and even deadly consequences. The title also hints at the idea that love itself can be a perilous emotion, capable of causing both great joy and great pain. Overall, the title of Dangerous Love serves as a warning to readers about the potential dangers of giving in to our most intense emotions, and the importance of exercising caution and restraint in matters of the heart.
Okri’s Use of Language and Imagery
Ben Okri’s Dangerous Love is a novel that is rich in language and imagery. The author’s use of language is poetic and evocative, and his descriptions of the characters and their surroundings are vivid and detailed. Okri’s writing style is characterized by a lyrical quality that draws the reader in and immerses them in the world of the novel.
One of the most striking aspects of Okri’s use of language is his ability to create powerful images that stay with the reader long after they have finished reading. For example, in one scene, the protagonist, Omovo, is described as being “like a bird with a broken wing, fluttering helplessly in the wind.” This image is both poignant and haunting, and it captures the sense of vulnerability and desperation that Omovo feels throughout the novel.
Another example of Okri’s use of imagery can be seen in his descriptions of the city of Lagos, where the novel is set. Okri paints a vivid picture of the city, with its bustling streets, crowded markets, and towering skyscrapers. He also captures the darker side of the city, with its poverty, crime, and corruption. Through his descriptions, Okri creates a sense of place that is both vivid and complex, and he invites the reader to explore the city alongside his characters.
Overall, Okri’s use of language and imagery is one of the strengths of Dangerous Love. His writing is both beautiful and powerful, and it adds depth and richness to the novel. Whether he is describing the characters, the setting, or the emotions that drive the story, Okri’s language is always evocative and engaging.
An official website of the United States government
Official websites use .gov A .gov website belongs to an official government organization in the United States.
Secure .gov websites use HTTPS A lock ( Lock Locked padlock icon ) or https:// means you've safely connected to the .gov website. Share sensitive information only on official, secure websites.
- Publications
- Account settings
- Advanced Search
- Journal List
Addicted to love: What is love addiction and when should it be treated?
Brian d earp, olga a wudarczyk, bennett foddy, julian savulescu.
- Author information
- Copyright and License information
Recent research suggests that romantic love can be literally addictive. Although the exact nature of the relationship between love and addiction has been described in inconsistent terms throughout the literature, we offer a framework that distinguishes between a narrow view and a broad view of love addiction. The narrow view counts only the most extreme, harmful forms of love or love-related behaviors as being potentially addictive in nature. The broad view, by contrast, counts even basic social attachment as being on a spectrum of addictive motivations, underwritten by similar neurochemical processes as more conventional addictions. We argue that on either understanding of love-as-addiction, treatment decisions should hinge on considerations of harm and well-being rather than on definitions of disease. Implications for the ethical use of anti-love biotechnology are considered.
Keywords: love, sex, addiction, oxytocin, psychiatry, well-being
“By nature we are all addicted to love … meaning we want it, seek it and have a hard time not thinking about it. We need attachment to survive and we instinctively seek connection, especially romantic connection. [But] there is nothing dysfunctional about wanting love.” – Smith, quoted in Berry (2013)
Introduction
Throughout the ages love has been rendered as an excruciating passion. Ovid was the first to proclaim: “I can’t live with or without you” ( Amores III, xi, 39)—a locution made famous to modern ears by the Irish band U2. Contemporary film expresses a similar sentiment: as Jake Gyllenhaal’s character famously says in Brokeback Mountain , “I wish I knew how to quit you.” And everyday speech, too, is rife with such expressions as “I need you” and “I’m addicted to you.” These widely-used phrases capture what many people know first-hand: that when we are in love, we feel an overwhelmingly strong attraction to another person—one that is persistent, urgent, and hard to ignore.
Love can be thrilling, but it can also be perilous. When our feelings are returned, we might feel euphoric. Other times, love’s pull is so strong that we might follow it even to the point of hardship or personal ruin ( Earp, Wudarczyk, Sandberg, and Savulescu 2013 ). Lovers can become distracted, unreliable, unreasonable, or even unfaithful. In the worst case, they can become deadly. In 2011, over 10% of murders in the United States were committed by the victim’s lover ( FBI 2011 ). When relationships come to an unwanted end, we feel pain, grief, and loss. We may even become depressed, or withdrawn from society ( Mearns 1991 ).
These phenomena—including cycles of alternating ecstasy and despair, desperate longing, and the extreme and sometimes damaging thoughts and behaviors that can follow from love’s loss—bear a resemblance to analogous phenomena associated with more “conventional” addictions like those for drugs, alcohol, or gambling. Nevertheless, although we do sometimes use the language of addiction when referring to love, there is at least one major feature that distinguishes love from the kinds of substance-based addictions typically described in the psychological and medical literature: nearly everyone aspires to fall in love at least once in their life. By contrast, nobody yearns to become addicted to heroin (for example), or cigarettes, or slot machines. So it might seem absurd on its face to suggest that there could be a real similarity between lovers and “genuine” addicts. Surely it is all just hyperbole and poetic license?
Addicted to love
Perhaps not. So numerous are the superficial similarities between addictive substance use and love- and sex-based interpersonal attachments, from exhilaration, ecstasy, and craving, to irregular physiological responses and obsessive patterns of thought, that a number of scientific theorists have begun to argue that both sorts of phenomena may rely upon similar or even identical psychological, chemical, and neuroanatomical substrates (e.g., Insel 2003 ; Fisher, Brown, Aron, Strong, and Mashek 2010 ; Burkett and Young 2012 ). 1
The past decade has seen a dramatic increase in published studies on the neurobiology and neurochemistry of romantic love (for overviews, see Savulescu and Sandberg 2008 ; Earp, Sandberg, and Savulescu 2012 ). Taken together, these studies suggest that the subjective state (or states) of “being in love” is intimately tied to characteristic biochemical reactions occurring within the brain. These reactions involve such compounds as dopamine, oxytocin, vasopressin, and serotonin and recruit brain regions known to play a role in the development of trust, the creation of feelings of pleasure, and the signalling of reward ( Esch and Stefano 2005 ). The involvement of similar neurochemicals and neural activities in processes associated with addiction has already been well established ( Blum, Chen, et al. 2012 ). Consequently, scientists have begun to draw a number of parallels between the naturally rewarding phenomena associated with human love and the artificial stimulation afforded by the use of addictive substances such as alcohol, heroin, or cocaine (see Frascella et al. 2010 ).
While the specific nature of these parallels has been described in inconsistent language throughout the literature, two main approaches to conceptualizing the relationship between love and addiction can be usefully teased out. The first approach counts only the most extreme cases (or phases) of love and love-related behaviors as being potential instances of addiction. Research in this vein focuses on sexual compulsions, paedophilia, toxic or abusive relationships, abnormal attachments and unhealthy tolerance of negative life- and relationship outcomes (e.g., Carnes 2005 ; Reynaud et al. 2010 ).
The second approach takes a wider view, and counts even “normal” romantic passions as being chemically and behaviorally analogous to addiction (e.g., Fisher et al. 2010 ; Burkett and Young, 2012 ). Studies in this vein emphasize the commonality between the experience of someone under the influence of certain drugs and the quite ordinary experience of someone in love—including her “focused attention” on a preferred individual, “mood swings, craving, obsession, compulsion, distortion of reality, emotional dependence, personality changes, risk-taking, and loss of self-control” ( Fisher et al. 2010 , 51). Burkett and Young ( 2012 , 1) go so far as to defend the hypothesis that basic social attachment – covering the whole course of love-based relationships from initiation to break-up – may be understood as a form of behavioral addiction “whereby the subject becomes addicted to another individual and the cues that predict social reward.”
In the following sections, we highlight some of the latest thinking on the nature of romantic love considered as an addiction, drawing on behavioral, neurophysiological, and neuroimaging studies of both love and addiction. By doing so, we hope to give a taste of, as well as to clarify, the existing evidence in favor of these differing accounts. Following that, we will attempt to explore some of the moral and practical implications that begin to emerge once we recognize that:
one can indeed become addicted to love, and
to be in love is in some sense to be addicted—i.e, to another person
Our main thesis will be that on either understanding of love-as-addiction, there is a reasonable case to be made that, in some instances, “treatment” of love could be justified or even desirable. We will also argue that respecting the lovers’ autonomy should be paramount in any treatment decision. Along the way, we will entertain some possible objections to our views, as well as offer our replies.
The narrow view: addiction as the result of abnormal brain processes
Although scholarly attitudes have been shifting in recent years, the dominant model of addictive drug use—among neuroscientists and psychiatrists, at least—is that drugs are addictive because they gradually elicit abnormal, unnatural patterns of function in the human brain ( Foddy and Savulescu 2010 ). On this ‘narrow’ view of addiction, addictive behaviors are produced by brain processes that simply do not exist in the brains of non-addicted persons. 2
One especially popular version of this view holds that drugs ‘co-opt’ neurotransmitters in the brain to create signals of reward that dwarf the strength of ‘natural rewards’ such as food or sex. They thereby produce patterns of learning and cellular adaptation in the brain that could never be produced without drugs (e.g. Volkow et al. 2010 ). According to this strict account, then, addictive drug-seeking is an aberrant form of behavior that is peculiar to drug addicts, both in form and in underlying function. It follows that natural rewards like food and love can never be truly addictive, and that food-seeking or love-seeking behaviors are not truly the result of addiction, no matter how addiction-like they may outwardly appear.
Other researchers, however, have noted appreciable behavioral similarities between binge-eaters (for example) and drug users, and have flagged a growing body of evidence that is suggestive of neurological similarities as well ( Foddy 2011 ). Sweet food, to take just one example, can elicit a reward signal in the brain as strong as the reward from a typical dose of cocaine ( Lenoir et al. 2007 ). In addition, it can even induce—at least in rats—a withdrawal syndrome as strong as that induced by heroin ( Avena et al. 2007 ). If an illicit drug like cocaine, therefore, can produce ‘abnormal’ brain processes by providing abnormal and chronic reward, then so might an abnormally high natural reward, like the reward one gets from bingeing on food, or from experiencing unusually strong or frequent feelings of love. Given these considerations, a more plausible ‘narrow’ view of love addiction would hold that one can indeed be addicted to love, but only if these abnormal brain processes are present.
Indeed, a number of addiction theorists have argued that otherwise harmless love-related phenomena can qualify as addictive if they take on such an ‘extreme’ or maladaptive form—termed “destructive” love by Fisher (2004) , and “unwise” or “desperate” love by Peele and Brodsky (1975) . One way to begin to understand love-related behaviors of this “destructive” type is to use the framework of process addiction ( Sussman 2010 ; Timmereck 1990). Process addiction—as opposed to substance addiction—typically refers to an obsession with certain activities such as sex, spending money, eating, or gambling. When a person in love repeatedly seeks contact with another individual—for physical intimacy, attention, or merely to be in the same room—it is often to secure momentary feelings of intense pleasure and to relieve obsessive thought patterns about the object of her passion. If this sort of behavior threatens the individual’s (or another’s) safety, mental or physical health, or incurs serious social or legal costs, it may rise to the level of an addiction (e.g., Sussman 2010 ).
A further distinction has been drawn by Sussman (2010) , following Curtis (1983) , between mature love and immature love. Sussman suggests that only the latter may be considered a form of addiction. Rather than permitting mutual growth within the partnership, or contributing to increased self-esteem and well-being in both individuals, immature love is typified by power games, possessive thoughts and behaviors, obsessive concern over the partner’s fidelity, “clinging” tendencies, uncertainty, and anxiety. Love-addicts on this model “feel desperate and alone when not in a relationship,” “continue trying to romance the love object long after the relationship has broken up,” and “replace ended relationships immediately” despite such declarations as “I’ll never love again” ( Sussman 2010 , 34).
To summarize, a lover might be suffering from a type of addiction (on this narrow view) if she expresses one of a number of abnormal sexual or attachment behaviors—perhaps underwritten by similarly abnormal brain processes—such that her quest for love (1) interferes with her ability to participate in the ordinary functions of everyday life, (2) disables her from experiencing healthy relationships, or (3) carries other clear negative consequences for herself or others. In the case of more ordinary examples of love—i.e., the ones to which most people probably aspire—these feelings, behaviors, and ill consequences are not present, or are present only to a mild or manageable degree.
The narrow view of love addiction is narrow , then, in the sense that it sees only extreme, radical brain processes, attachment behaviors, or manifestations of love as being potentially indicative of addiction—and hence it is thought to be quite rare. For example, Timmereck (1990) has estimated that love addiction of this type may affect between 5-10% of the U.S population. By contrast, “healthy” romantic love, which is assumed to be much more common, is described by scholars such as Sussman (2010) as being benign or even beneficial. Such love is said to have evolved, for example, for adaptive (and still-useful) ends, such as the promotion of procreative behaviors and the facilitation of cognitive and social learning. Reynaud et al. ( 2010 , 262) distinguish between love addiction and mere “love passion” which they describe as “a universal and necessary state for human beings.” And Peele and Brodsky (1975) refer to “genuine” love, which, unlike the self-seeking dependency associated with addictive love, involves a commitment to mutual growth and fulfillment between the partners involved.
As we explore in the following section, however, other researchers, notably Burkett and Young (2012) , have begun to highlight the similarities between addiction and even “normal” romantic relationships by emphasizing the common behavioral, neurophysiological, and neurochemical signatures of both.
The broad view: love as addiction
There is a broader understanding of addiction that has been gaining steam in recent years. As two of us have argued, addiction should be considered to be a spectrum of motivation that emerges from the repeated application of any type of reward, including drug rewards, gambling rewards, food rewards, and sexual rewards (Foddy and Savulescu 2006, 2010 ; Foddy 2011 ). These appetite-motivations arise in response to reward conditioning, and are, indeed, the evolved mechanism by which we humans and other animals learn to behave in survival- and reproduction-enhancing ways. At the same time, such appetites do not always lead directly to these “evolutionary” outcomes, especially in humans, and even more so in the modern environment we have created for ourselves (see Earp, Sandberg, and Savulescu 2012 ). Our appetite for food, for example, is not strictly genetically controlled: we are weaned onto it during gestation, and it can wax and wane over the course of our lives, often in ways that run contrary to our real nutritive needs ( Foddy 2011 ). By the same token, we may develop appetites for any rewarding behavior, and these appetites may exceed or fall beneath a level that suits our biological needs, our conscious values, or our personal preferences.
On a broad view, then, addictions are simply appetites: they are felt needs that can be temporarily satisfied, but which become urgent and distracting if one abstains from fulfilling them for too long. Conversely, and perhaps counterintuitively, appetites are simply weak addictions. At least on this account, then, everyone is ‘addicted’ to food, to sex, and to other ordinary substances and behaviors, although most of us are not ‘hooked’ on them to such a degree as to cause us any major harm or distress or to merit the application of a psychiatric diagnosis or treatment (see Foddy and Savulescu 2010 , for a sustained defence of this view).
A similar broad approach can be applied to the concept of love addiction. This approach would claim that to love someone is literally to be addicted to them, though perhaps only weakly. In line with this view, James Burkett and Larry Young (2012) have recently argued that romantic relationships experienced universally—from “falling in love” to ultimate separation and subsequent withdrawal—may be considered a form of addiction. To prime the reader for their thesis, they open their seminal paper on this subject with the following vignette:
At first, each encounter was accompanied by a rush of euphoria—new experiences, new pleasures, each more exciting than the last. Every detail became associated with those intense feelings: places, times, objects, faces. Other interests suddenly became less important as more time was spent pursuing the next joyful encounter. Gradually, the euphoria during these encounters waned, replaced imperceptibly by feelings of contentment, calm, and happiness. The moments between encounters seemed to grow longer, even as they stayed the same, and separation came to be filled with painful longing and desire. When everything was brought to an abrupt end, desperation and grief followed, leading slowly into depression. ( Burkett and Young 2012 , 1)
Does this story describe falling in love or becoming addicted to a drug? Burkett and Young’s point, of course, is that it could equally describe both. Drawing on evidence from animal models along with parallel research in human attachment and the neurobiology of substance abuse, they conclude that there is “a deep and systematic concordance … between the brain regions and neurochemicals involved in both addiction and social attachment” ( Burkett and Young 2012 , 2).
In other words, substance dependence and everyday romantic bonding have much more in common than their outward psychological profiles. At the level of the brain, the mechanisms underlying pair-bonding in socially monogamous or quasi-monogamous species (such as humans) overlap quite substantially with those involved in reward learning and addiction (see, e.g., Wise 1996 ). The greatest overlap occurs in neurochemical regions involved in the processing of dopamine ( Kelley and Berridge 2002 ; Burkett and Young 2012 ) oxytocin ( Insel 2003 ; McGregor, Callagham and Hunt 2008 ), and other neurotransmitters such as serotonin. As Margolis ( 2005 , x) states: “… through sex [with our partner], orgasm’s serotonin rush and momentary muscular relaxation comprise the most potent and popular drug we have.”
With respect to dopamine, both mating and addictions elicit very similar neurochemical activity, concentrated in the reward circuitry of the brain: sex, orgasm, and all known drugs of abuse stimulate high levels dopamine release in the nucleus accumbens (see Burkett and Young 2012 , Kirsch et al. 2006 , and Di Chiara et al. 2004 for more information). In fact, the role of dopamine extends far beyond addiction and is linked to a wide range of other processes associated with reward-learning—including eating, drinking, having sexual intercourse, and love (see Burkett and Young 2012 , for a review). Some scientists have suggested that this dopaminergic overlap may explain why experiencing love or engaging in sexual activity can feel like a cocaine rush ( Blum, Wernel, et al. 2012 ; Bartels and Zeki 2000 ).
Finally, neuroimaging support for an overlap between love-addiction and drug-addiction comes from studies in which participants have been exposed to images of their romantic partners during scanning. These images evoke not only self-reported feelings of love and positive affect but also show heavy activation in brain’s reward regions ( Aron et al. 2005 ; Bartels and Zeki 2000 ; Young 2009; Fisher et al. 2006 ).
These are just a few of the neurochemical and functional similarities between “normal” love attachment and drug addiction that have been noted by Burkett and Young as well as by other researchers who argue for the “broader” view of love addiction. There are many others as well. But what about differences between love and addiction? Surely the numerous “parallels” between these phenomena—at both the behavioral and neural levels—should not be taken to mean that they are strictly equivalent. In the following section, we examine some of these differences, and assess their implications for the “broad” vs. “narrow” debate.
What about differences?
Although there is a significant amount of “concordance” between love and addiction on several levels of analysis, there are some important differences between naturally rewarding activities (such as those associated with being in love) and the artificial stimulation of the reward system that occurs during drug use. As we will see, however, these differences are less significant—in terms of establishing a distinction in kind between love-based and drug-based addiction—than they may seem at first glance.
One such difference, at the level of the brain, concerns the duration of the effects of the stimulus. The release of signalling molecules in case of love-related experiences—such as sexual intercourse—may not be as long lasting as the analogous release stimulated by the use of addictive drugs ( Esch and Stefano 2005 ). Natural rewards are highly controlled by feedback mechanisms, which may lead to a quicker return to “baseline” by promoting (for example) an aversion to engaging in the same rewarding activity immediately after the pleasant stimulation ( Small, Zatorre, Dagher, Evans, and Jones-Gotman 2001 ). For example, the building-up of sexual desire often precedes a sexual act (e.g., Heaton and Adams 2003 ), after which it quickly decreases and then takes time to recover its initial level of intensity. Addictive stimulants, on the other hand, often rebuild high levels of desire immediately after drug consumption (e.g., Nestler 2005 ). From this it is often argued that drug-seeking activities override other motivations more easily than activities associated with the pursuit of “natural” rewards ( Esch and Stefano 2004 ).
Even granting this view, however, it must be remembered that the neurodynamics of even “conventional” addictive drugs are not all the same, since their mechanisms of action vary so widely ( Nestler 2005 ). Non-stimulant drugs such as alcohol, opiates, and benzodiazepines, for example, are not as quick to rekindle cravings as stimulants are, and they can even induce an appetitive regret that is similar to the regret lovers experience as “post-coital malaise” (cf. Le Moal and Koob 2007 ; Norville, Sweeney, and Elliott 2010 ). More importantly, the feedback mechanisms that control the processing of “natural” rewards are not always reliable, nor are the neurological signals from natural rewards always weak. Some 3% of American adults suffer from binge-eating disorder, in which their complex satiety system, which should alert them to the state of being full, is so dysregulated that these individuals can regularly eat enormous quantities of food in a fevered “binge’ ( Foddy 2011 ). When these same individuals binge on sugary food, they can experience a level of neurological reward that surpasses a dose of a drug such as cocaine ( Lenoir et al. 2007 ). The evidence, therefore, suggesting that drugs of abuse are inherently better-suited to causing addiction than are other types of reward is mixed at best.
How else might “being in love” be taken to differ from being addicted to certain drugs? For one thing, while drug addiction is a circumscribed problem, affecting a mere fraction of the global population, romantic love is a universal phenomenon, emerging from basic, evolved sub-systems that helped our ancestors pursue mating opportunities with preferred partners (see Savulescu and Sandberg 2008 ). In other words, love is deeply bound up with reproduction, which is the engine of natural selection ( Blum, Chen, et al. 2012 ). Drug use, by contrast, serves no clear function with respect to survival or reproduction, and it has often been described as ‘hijacking’ mechanisms underpinning the natural reward functions of the brain, supplanting more ‘adaptive’ behaviors with entirely artificial ones that are irrelevant to genetic fitness ( Hyman 2007 ). Taking a complementary view, Fisher (2004) has argued that romantic love might be considered a ‘constructive’ form of addiction when one’s love is reciprocated; whereas it is presumed that drug addiction would never be constructive. And while we can flourish without ever taking drugs, we cannot do so if deprived of food, or, indeed, some measure of love and human affection.
However, these considerations do not entail that love addiction, food addiction, and drug addiction are different in kind. Binge-eating is in fact extremely detrimental to one’s chances for long-term survival, just as extreme forms of love-related phenomena—such as an insatiable appetite for sex—can lead to such negative outcomes as interpersonal problems, sexually transmitted diseases, loss of employment, or even imprisonment ( Carnes 2005 ). No extreme pattern of reward-seeking, whether it is for food, sex, romantic love, or drugs, is likely to promote a person’s chances of flourishing in the modern world—and any normal capacity can be taken to extremes (see Earp, Sandberg, Kahane, and Savulescu 2014 ).
Moreover, although a moderate appetite for so-called ‘natural’ rewards is quite plainly beneficial, it would not be unreasonable to make a similar claim regarding certain drugs to which people can sometimes become addicted—at least if we view pleasure as being one important source of the good. Nobody strictly needs drugs to flourish, but in some circumstances, and for some people, some non-therapeutic drugs could certainly be considered compatible with human flourishing if taken within reason, such as the moderate consumption of alcohol.
Finally, there is the fact that love must be requited for it to deliver its full benefit. Lovers rarely regret being in love if the love is returned, and indeed a significant part of the suffering associated with falling in love stems from romantic rejection , or withdrawal of love—rather than from love itself. Substance addicts, by contrast, are never rejected by their drug in the same way, so perhaps there is a difference in this regard as well. Even so, there are some potential parallels on this dimension that complicate the notion that love addiction and drug addiction are totally incommensurable phenomena.
For example, consider the fact that the difficulty of obtaining drugs can be the source of many (if not most) of the problems that drug addicts experience. Access to drugs is constrained by scarcity, cost, illegality, and social stigmatization in addition to any biological (side) effects. Some of the destructiveness of drug addiction occurs because an addict is unable to afford her drug and turns to crime; because her friends and family reject her for taking a drug; or because she cannot obtain her drug and goes into withdrawal. The addiction itself is not clearly the cause of most of the associated harms. Therefore, we can draw at least a tenuous analogy here, too, between a lover who is rejected and a drug user who cannot access her drug of addiction.
Taken together, these considerations show that while there are indeed some differences between love-based and drug-based addictions, these differences may have more to do with the frequency of problems at the population level, or with the typical degree of reward-stimulation involved in particular cases, than with any clear incommensurability in kind. 3
Broad or Narrow?
The behavioral, psychological, and neurophysiological evidence concerning love, love-related phenomena, drugs of addiction, and the parallels between them, paint a very complicated and hotly-debated picture. Just within the drug addiction literature—holding “love addiction” to the side—there is little agreement about whether the “narrow view” or the “broad view” of addiction is to be preferred. In other words, there is (as yet) no meaningful consensus about whether it is the case that addictive drug-related desires are (a) of an unnatural form that is not present in the non-addict (the narrow view); or (b) whether they are on a continuum with “regular” appetitive desires, and therefore simply a strong form of the same underlying phenomenon (the broad view). The available neuroscientific and behavioral evidence simply cannot settle the question firmly one way or the other.
The same is true regarding “love addiction.” Should only the most extreme, compulsive, or harmful love-related phenomena be considered potential forms of addiction? Or, as Burkett and Young (2012) have recently suggested, might it be the case that there is a neurological equivalence between quite ordinary experiences associated with falling in love—and even basic social attachment itself—and addictions of a more conventional stripe? Much more work is needed, we suggest, both empirical and conceptual, to arbitrate between these differing views.
At a minimum, however, the evidence we have discussed in this article suggests that drug addiction, on the one hand, and at least certain love-related experiences or behaviors, on the other, can reasonably be understood to be equivalent phenomena at the level of the brain, underwritten by the same neurophysiological processes. If this is correct, it cannot be the case that (narrow) addiction is a phenomenon confined to addictive drugs. Holders of the narrow view must instead claim that addiction is a term we can apply to any person who has undergone chronic and unusually strong (pleasurable) experiences—intense drug-reward in the case of drug addicts, food binges in the case of binge-eaters, or powerful personal attachments in the case of love addicts.
Based on this premise, in the next section, we will explore some of the practical and ethical implications that arise when we acknowledge that love has (or can have) addictive characteristics, at least on the narrow view, but also possibly on the broad view as well.
Ethical implications: two mysteries
The science and philosophy of addiction—generally speaking—have sought to solve two basic mysteries. The solution to these mysteries, in the case of love-addiction as much as for any other purported form of addiction, will have important practical and ethical implications.
First, we have sought to learn whether, or to what degree, those who suffer from addictions are capable of abstaining from or moderating their reward-seeking behavior; and second, we have been very interested to know whether—and how—we can help people to recover from addiction using various treatment modalities. We will consider these “mysteries” in turn as they relate to the notion of love addiction in the following sections.
Autonomy and responsibility
The first longstanding mystery concerning addiction in general is whether addicts are capable of abstaining from or moderating their drug use or other problematic behaviors. The solution to this mystery would have some indirect implications for the medical treatment of addicts, but it has much stronger philosophical and ethical implications: for example, is it reasonable to force addicts to abstain? It is reasonable to hold them morally or criminally responsible for their drug-taking? What about for illegal actions they committed in pursuit of their drug? These deep empirical and conceptual problems date back at least as far as the time of Plato, who wondered how a responsible person could continue to choose courses of action that she would predictably come to regret.
Naturally, this issue does not apply to love in the same way as it does to substance addiction or to other problematic behaviors. We do not ordinarily choose to love someone (at least not consciously) and it would be a hard thesis to defend that we should be held responsible for falling in love—even though such an occurrence can have very far-reaching, and sometimes destructive, consequences for those involved. We cannot criminalize falling in love, and though history is replete with stories of people having been punished for falling in love with the “wrong” person, such punishment would seem cruel or even absurd by today’s standards. 4
However, while the formation of love seems to be at least largely involuntary, there is a real question regarding how autonomous one’s behavior is once one is, in fact, in love. People who are in love make choices every day about how to express their feelings: whether to seek proximity with their loved one, or physical affection; whether to make expressions of their attachment a matter of public notice, and so on.
If addictive love is nothing more than a symptom of abnormal brain processes (i.e., the narrow view), then the choices and behaviors it elicits might be considered to be inauthentic or in some sense non-autonomous reflexes of those deviant processes. Hence, proponents of the narrow view of substance addiction have frequently argued that addicts lack control over their actions and are not fully autonomous ( Hyman 2007 ). This idea is also reflected in the common concept of “crimes of passion”— and indeed the law has traditionally taken such passion into account in sentencing decisions.
If this is the correct view, then we might think that it would be reasonable to try to eliminate the problematic feelings and behaviors associated with addictive love, since they are merely the symptoms of disease. And we might even believe that we could be justified in using coercion or force to prevent a love addict from being near the object of her desire. An analogous view is held by scholars such as Caplan, who have argued that we are justified in overriding a drug addict’s choices in the name of restoring her autonomy ( Caplan 2008 ). Indeed, we, too, have previously argued that in some domestic abuse situations, including Stockholm Syndrome-like cases of attachment between the victim and her abuser, coercive intervention may possibly be justifiable ( Earp, Wudarczyk, Sandberg, and Savulescu 2013 ).
The broad view, by contrast, argues that even the strongest, most negative forms of love are merely extremes of an authentic emotion. Hence it is possible to argue, from these grounds, that even those people who suffer from harmful extremes of love may be fully autonomous in their behavior. On this kind of view, any possible treatment modality would then differ along certain dimensions. The goal should not be to eliminate the feelings of love entirely, since those feelings are authentic aspects of the person’s mind and personality; but rather it should be to moderate them instead. Likewise, treatments should never violate the autonomy of the person-in-love, nor should they involve coercion or force of any kind. Two of us have advanced a similar point of view regarding treatment for substance addiction ( Foddy and Savulescu 2010 ).
Treatment and recovery
These considerations bring us to the second “mystery” concerning addiction, namely whether treatment is appropriate or advisable and whether recovery is possible. Although one would not normally think of offering “treatment” to individuals who are in love, once we begin to realize that at least some cases of love and love-related phenomena are similar to behavioral or substance addictions—in form, function, as well as in effect—then the possibility becomes worth taking seriously. Indeed, the idea of an anti-love remedy or a “cure” for love has deep historical roots. As we noted in a recent paper ( Earp, Wudarczyk, Sandberg, and Savulescu 2013 , 3): “references [to such ‘cures’] may be found in the writings of Lucretius, Ovid, Shakespeare, and many others, and are tightly linked to the notion that love or infatuation—under certain conditions—can be just like a serious illness: bad for one’s physical and mental health and, in some cases, profoundly damaging to one’s overall well-being.”
In other words, the possibility of treating love—given the right sort of circumstances—may not be so far-fetched after all. Importantly, the way in which we approach this possibility will depend upon whether we subscribe to the broad view or the narrow view of “love addiction” as outlined above. Yet as we show in what follows, the general conclusion of such an analysis may not differ very much in the end, regardless of the view one takes. That is, love addiction— however it is conceived —would seem to be an appropriate candidate for treatment in at least some circumstances. Or so we argue in this section.
Recall: the narrow view considers that love is only an addiction (or at least addiction-like) in rare or abnormal cases, generated either by pre-existing pathophysiology or by chronic ultra-strong “doses” of love-based reward. On this kind of view, love addiction is a neurobiological disorder that has no place in a healthy or flourishing life, and it follows that we ought to offer love addicts some measure of treatment or support. Furthermore, on the narrow view, we might expect that the best course of action is a standard psychiatric treatment modality, in which we try to restore normal neurophysiology using psychiatric drugs and/or cognitive therapy (see Earp, Sandberg and Savulescu 2015 ). For example, just as heroin addicts are sometimes given oral naltrexone to block the pharmacological effects of their drug, we could use oxytocin antagonists to reduce the reward an individual receives from being close to another person (see Earp, Wudarczyk, Sandberg, and Savulescu 2013 ).
According to the broad view, by contrast, everyone who loves is on a spectrum of addictive conditions: being addicted to another person is not an illness but simply the result of a fundamental human capacity that can sometimes be exercised to excess. On this kind of view, it can be objected that love—no matter how destructive—is never an appropriate object of psychiatric treatment. A similar notion is that we now know that homosexuality is within the range of normal human variation and is therefore not appropriately considered a “disease.”
Yet this is where the distinction between broad and narrow begins to break down. On both views, that is, the primary difficulty from an ethical point of view is to determine how we ought to distinguish the good kinds of love from the bad: the innocuous or even the beneficial from the dangerous and the harmful. As one of us has argued, in cases of mental illness it can be very difficult to sort pathology from normal function, especially in the grey areas between extremes ( Savulescu 2009 ). Current theories of brain function are nowhere near advanced enough to tell us whether a particular individual’s emotions fall within statistical norms; and even if science could tell us such a thing, we would still need to make value judgments in order to define which part of the statistical curve is desirable. For example, we arbitrarily define anyone with an IQ two standard deviations below the mean as being intellectually disabled—and hence deserving of special treatment—but we could just as easily have put the bar at one standard deviation, or three.
Nearly every psychiatric disability or disease represents an extreme of a smooth spectrum of behavior, function, or capacity. Not all sad people are depressed, and not all energetic people are manic. Our definitions of psychiatric illness, therefore, are essentially holistic rather than purely naturalistic; they are based inevitably on judgments of value—or in other words, ethical judgments. At base, these judgements relate certain states of biology or psychology to well-being: when a state either constitutes or creates harm, it may come to be defined as a disease and thereby mark itself out as a candidate for treatment. 5
Given this inherent value-ladenness, we suggest, in defining some condition as a disease or a disorder, we should consider a range of different outcomes that would result from the application of such a label. We must consider who we think should have excuses for their behavior; who should receive support from friends or from the state; who should be an object of medical research; and (above all) who should receive treatment . These outcomes must be assessed on a range of moral and practical grounds, such as the suffering experienced by the afflicted person; the degree to which her ‘addiction’ undermines her ability to act on her preferences or execute her plans; and the extent to which it compromises important social relationships, impedes the development of her talents, impoverishes her interaction with the world, and so on.
In line with this view, consider the definition of substance dependence from the latest available (at the time of writing) edition of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders from the American Psychological Association, the DSM-IV: “When an individual persists in use of alcohol or other drugs despite problems related to use of the substance , substance dependence may be diagnosed” ( American Psychiatric Association 2000 , emphasis added). As this quotation makes plain, the existence of “problems”—a normative concept—is inherent in the definition of the disorder. In other words, it matters fundamentally whether harm, difficulty, or ill-consequences are associated with the reward-seeking behavior: the reward itself is not the problem. Furthermore, and consistent with our arguments in this paper, addiction theorist Stanton Peele (quoted in Curley 2010 ) has suggested that next edition of the DSM—volume 5—should include “life-harming, compulsive” involvement with sources of reward such as sex and food in the category of addiction. Here, too, the notion of “life-harm” is built into the very concept of the disorder in question.
What insight do these considerations bring to our understanding of love addiction and its potential for being an appropriate subject of treatment? The message by now should be clear: regardless of whether we understand the love-related phenomenon to be the result of abnormal brain processes, or simply the manifestation of a strong appetitive desire, the key determinant for labelling and treatment should be the degree to which the individual is harmed by the love through its deleterious impact on her well-being. In the next section, we examine this perspective in greater detail.
Love addiction and well-being
There are three main theories of well-being—or classes of theories—discussed throughout the literature ( Griffin 1986 ; Parfit 1984 ). How one relates love addiction to well-being, and therefore to treatment, will depend upon the theory (or theories) of well-being one finds most convincing.
The first class of theories concerning well-being are hedonistic theories , which are defined in terms of mental states. The simplest account of this type of view is that happiness, or pleasure (understood broadly as a mental state) is the only intrinsic good, whereas unhappiness or pain is the only intrinsic bad. More complex hedonistic views include a greater plurality of states of mind as possibly contributing to (or constituting) well being: for example, Freud is reputed to have refused analgesia when dying of cancer—although he was in great physical pain—on the grounds that he preferred to be able to think clearly in a state of torment than foggedly in a state of drug-induced comfort (see Griffin 1986 ).
Yet however one construes 6 this hedonistic mental-state view, it is clearly possible that a person could prefer to exist in a rapturous state of love, even though it might yield a number of adverse consequences in other areas of her life, due to its irrefutably high, intrinsic hedonic value. Indeed, in Western societies, being in love is widely considered to be an extremely valuable state, and possibly constitutive of a good life all on its own. This notion is captured in the ideal of “dying for love” with the implication that such a love might even be the very meaning of life.
The second class of theories concerning well-being are desire-fulfilment theories. According to these theories, well being consists in having one’s desires fulfilled. They give weight to individual values and yet they account for the plurality of values that might differ across individuals: economic theories commonly employ a related notion of value, and such accounts are widespread in philosophy and in the social sciences in general. On the most plausible desire-fulfilment theories, desires should be informed (of the relevant facts) as well as freely devised—that is, not forced upon one in any way—in order to count toward one’s well-being.
Could love addiction be consistent with well-being on this desire-fulfilment account? It does seem possible. Specifically, if a person desired, freely, to exist in a state of extreme passion—even granting certain negative outcomes—while nevertheless being fully informed about the nature of addictive love, how it might affect her brain (and so on), then love addiction and well-being might indeed coincide in such a person. On this view, treatment might not be appropriate, even though negative consequences were present.
Finally, there are objective list theories of well-being. According to these theories (sometimes called substantive good or perfectionistic theories), certain things can be good or bad for a person—and thus contribute to her well being—whether or not they are desired and whether or not they lead to a “pleasurable” mental state. Examples of the sorts of things that have been proposed as being intrinsically good in this way are: gaining knowledge, having deep personal relationships (including being in love), engaging in rational activity, and developing one’s abilities. Examples of “objectively” bad things include: being betrayed, being deceived, and gaining pleasure from cruelty.
On this type of theory, it might be harder to square love addiction with any genuine sort of well-being—especially on the “narrow” view. That is, one could plausibly argue that only “normal” or “healthy” or “constructive” kinds of love are objectively constitutive of well-being, whereas love that is extreme, compulsive, resultant from abnormal brain processes, or that carries negative consequences for one’s health or for other social relationships is objectively bad for one. If this were the case, then such a love could potentially be deserving of some form of treatment under the right conditions.
Yet what theory of well-being should one accept? Unsurprisingly, philosophers have long noted that each of the theories of well being outlined above capture something important and intuitive about what is needed to live a good life, but all have problems as well. Accordingly, many philosophers opt for a composite theory in which well-being is seen as requiring at least certain aspects of all of the theories. On this composite view, then, well-being is constituted by engaging in objectively worthwhile activities, which we desire, and which provide us with pleasure or other valuable mental states ( Savulescu 2007 ).
To summarize, love will clearly be an important component of any plausible theory of well-being. However, on a composite view, especially one which incorporates aspects of the objective-list account, love that entails insufferable pain, that frustrates other important desires, or that stops one from engaging in objectively worthwhile activities, might reasonably be taken to compromise well-being. The best life is not one that consumed by destructive or mal-adaptive forms of love, but is rather one in which love finds a robust harmony with other sources of the good.
Implications for treatment
What does all of this mean for treatment? With respect to the narrow view of love addiction, it means that we will need to make an ethical judgment about how narrow the diagnostic category should be. How strong or destructive does love have to be to qualify as addictive love? On the broad view, we face a similar challenge. Although it is that case that, on this view, everyone who loves is technically addicted, only some subset of cases should be judged to be appropriate candidates for treatment because of their effect(s) on other aspects of our well-being. Though the two views take radically different stances on the neurobiological underpinnings of problematic love, it is still the case that for both views it is the negative consequences or harm of the ‘bad love’ that determine whether the person or people involved should be considered appropriate subjects for the application of some remedy.
To reiterate: the primary diagnostic criterion for love addiction, in our view, should not depend very much on whether we agree with the narrow or the broad interpretations of the available neuropsychological evidence. Instead our allocations of medical and social care should be informed by an appeal to how much a person is made to suffer (or to experience other threats to well-being) through his or her experience of love ( Kahane and Savulescu 2009 ). If we determine that medical or social intervention could be of benefit to a person, then it will be at least potentially appropriate to offer some degree of treatment or support.
How would it work? The prospect of anti-love biotechnology
Treatment of love addiction, like any other form of addiction, could take many forms. The most plausible starting place would be “traditional” therapies such as professional counselling, cognitive-behavioral techniques, psychoanalysis, or some combination of these and other widely-used treatment modalities that work primarily on the psycho-behavioral level (see Earp, Sandberg, and Savulescu 2015 ). At the same time, considering the recent surge of research focusing on possible neurobiological sources of love addiction, it may soon be possible to devise adjunctive drug-based therapies that could facilitate treatment of problematic forms of love by working on underlying neurochemical substrates. In a recent paper ( Earp, Wudarczyk, Sandberg, and Savulescu 2013 ), we identified four conditions for the ethical use of such anti-love biotechnology:
the love in question is clearly harmful and needs to dissolve one way or another;
the person would want to use the technology, so there would be no problematic violations of consent;
the technology would help the person follow her higher-level goals and commitments instead of her lower-level feelings;
it might not be psychologically possible to overcome the perilous feelings without the help of anti-love biotechnology—or at least non-biotechnological methods had been already tried or thoroughly considered
In addition, we have suggested that any drug-based treatment of love or love-related phenomena should be undertaken only under the guidance of a trained professional, and only once the safety and efficacy of such treatment had been established via rigorous clinical testing ( Wudarczyk, Earp, Guastella, and Savulescu 2013 ). Moreover, we have argued that such technologies should not be used on minors, i.e., before an age of consent (see Earp, Sandberg, and Savulescu 2014 ).
Concluding remarks
In this article, we have argued that there is now abundant behavioral, neurochemical and neuroimaging evidence to support the claim that love is (or at least that it can be) an addiction, in much the same way that chronic drug-seeking behavior can be termed an addiction. And we have argued that no matter how we interpret this evidence, we should conclude that people whose lives are negatively impacted by love ought to be offered support and treatment opportunities analogous to those that we extend to substance abusers.
It must be acknowledged that by suggesting any sort of equivalence between love, which is culturally admired above all other emotions (or relational states), and addictive drugs, which are deeply and almost universally demonized, we are raising a comparison that many will find off-putting or even offensive. In Western society, we hold love—or even just falling in love—in very high esteem. To speak of romantic passion and destructive drug use in the same breath might only serve to conjure images of punishing people for falling in love, stigmatizing them, or forcing them out of their lover’s arms and into a treatment program. We do agree that these would be inappropriate, and even dangerous ways to treat people who are suffering from a harmful sort of love or love gone bad.
But if falling in love is not so different, behaviorally or biologically, from developing a drug habit or a binge-eating problem, then perhaps this recognition could afford us an opportunity to deeply interrogate our views about the inherent harms of addiction. Perhaps, instead of taking on the view that love must be harmful if it is addictive, we could take the reverse view, and wonder if even substance addictions might be not always be strictly harmful under the right sorts of conditions. At least in principle, it would seem that drug addiction could even be good for us if the drug were plentiful, safe, and legal, in much the same way that, on the converse, romantic love may be bad for us if the object of our affection is cruel, or unfaithful, or uninterested. If the evidence shows that the two phenomena are identical or even just substantially overlapping in nature, then perhaps we should revisit our attitudes to both. The ultimate goal, whether the subject is drug-use or romantic passion, should be to identify those cases in which the behavior and its related phenomena cause harm and suffering to those involved. And any treatment that is pursued—on either the narrow view or the broad view of addiction—should be undertaken in such a way that the decision-making autonomy of the lovers is given maximal consideration.
Acknowledgements
The authors would like to thank Allan McKennna, Sven Nyholm, Maia Szalavitz, Michael Mascolo, Matthew Broome, and two anonymous reviewers for feedback on an earlier draft of this manuscript. While we could not incorporate all of their important insights, we think the paper is much improved by the ones we did, and we have certainly been inspired to think more deeply about these complex issues. Work on this manuscript was supported by a Wellcome Trust grant #08604/Z/08/Z.
We are careful to note that just because two higher-level phenomena concerning human behaviour (and/or subjective experience) may involve similar, e.g., neurochemical mechanisms does not (by itself) show that they are “really” the same phenomenon—just as two events having similar causes doesn’t mean that they are same event. Much depends on the level of analysis one is concerned with, and how one conceptualizes the two phenomena at each relevant level. For further discussion, see our paper, “Neuroreductionism about sex and love” ( Savulescu and Earp 2014 ).
This has also been called the “brain disease” model of addiction (see Levy 2013 for a critique). As a reviewer for this paper notes, “Some supporters of [the] disease model of substance addiction think that addiction is literally a brain disease, while others incline to think of it as a behavioural disposition towards excessive and/or harmful consumption – a disposition that does not literally take away control over consumption, even though it may seem that way to the addict. [This raises] important questions … about whether addiction can really be ‘treated’ at all (for example, according to the ‘Rational Recovery’ approach to alcoholism, you can no more ‘treat’ drinking than you can ‘treat’ dancing; both are voluntary activities, though addicts find it much harder to stop).” As we make clear in our paper, even if love addiction is understood as being a behavioral disposition that makes it hard for one to avoid causing harm (to oneself or others), “treatment”—in the sense of a structured intervention, undertaken with the guidance of a trained professional (whether this involves the use of ‘medical’ technologies or not, see Earp, Sandberg and Savulescu 2015 )—could be justified under the right conditions.
At the conceptual level, of course, there may be other differences as well. As a reviewer notes, “One might argue that love aims at union with another person, whereas drug use aims at consumption; one could [also] say that a proper understanding of love must be holistic in a way that understanding drug use need not be. (For example, if we say that someone is in love, that suggests they have a range of concepts – of a person, of reciprocity and individuality – that need not be attributed to someone with an urge to consume a substance). [Finally, the] typical aims of romantic love – most obviously, the desire to be loved in return – [are not necessarily] true of consumption, whether of a person or of a drug.” We do not disagree with these observations. However, we have deliberately kept our philosophical account of love “thin” because there is no authoritative definition to which we could appeal (see Earp, Wudarczyk, Sandberg, and Savulescu 2013 ), and because we expect that different readers will have very different notions of what love “really is” (in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions) at the highest level of conceptual analysis. Thus we speak of “love-related” behaviors or feelings, which can be reasonably well explained in terms of neurobiology or lower-level functional mechanisms, and we leave it to the reader to decide what the implications are for his or her own philosophical conception of love. For further discussion, see Earp, Sandberg, and Savulescu (2015) .
There is an interesting question here about the extent to which people can influence their own likelihood of forming a love-based attachment with another person. Certainly there are enabling behaviors and conditions, and a person might very well have the power to shape these variables in such a way as to enhance, or diminish, the likelihood of falling in love with a particular person. Indeed, in arranged marriages, such as are common in some non-Western contexts, the partners might consciously (and intentionally) engage in activities, behaviors, and ways of thinking that allow for love to develop over time. Referring to such cases, Erich Fromm (1956) famously argued that love should not be thought of as something that one “falls into” but rather as a capacity (or even an art) that one learns to develop and to exercise. Nevertheless, even if one concludes that people cannot really “make themselves” fall in love, as a reviewer notes, they can make a choice as to whether they will love “unconditionally” – that is, “weather the storms of loving another person.” As this reviewer writes, “It takes voluntary commitment to love enduringly [and] autonomy may [actually] be enhanced by such commitments.” For further discussion, see Frankfurt (2004) .
It is important here to distinguish between physical and psychiatric disease. Physical disease is characterised by clear pathology. Naturalistic or “biostatistical accounts” such as that advocated by Boorse (1997) may be the best account of physical disease. However, there is no clear pathology in many psychiatric diseases at present. In practice, defining some mental state as a disease typically involves consideration of the impact of that state on a person’s life. This notion will serve as a backbone for our ethical arguments in the sections following this endnote marker.
A central issue for pluralistic accounts of hedonism is which mental states are to be included in an account of well being. Two types of answer to this question have been given: one is preference hedonism (or subjective hedonism), which states that the valuable mental states are those that are, as a matter of fact, desired. As Sidgwick (1874/1962, 127) wrote: “I propose therefore to define Pleasure … as a feeling which, when experienced by intelligent beings, is at least implicitly apprehended as desirable, or – in cases of comparison – preferable.” The second way in which mental states might be ascribed a value is to propose that some mental states are objectively valuable. Objectively valuable mental states are typically said to include fulfilment; calm; peace; hope; the experience of love and friendship ; happiness; and a sense of achievement. On any plausible hedonistic account of well-being, therefore, love will be high up on the list of valuable mental states. Of course its value could be offset by disvaluable mental states, such as pain. However, many people would interpret the pain associated with “true” love as being possibly un-entangleable from its depth, meaning, and value.
- American Psychiatric Association . Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-IV-TR. American Psychiatric Publishing, Inc.; Arlington: 2000. [ Google Scholar ]
- American Psychiatric Association APA announces draft diagnostic criteria for DSM-5 Disorders (press release) 2010 Accessed at: http://www.dsm5.org/Newsroom/Documents/Diag%20%20Criteria%20General%20FINAL%202.05.pdf .
- Aron A, Fisher H, Mashek DJ, Strong G, Li H, Brown LL. Reward, motivation, and emotion systems associated with early-stage intense romantic love. Journal of Neurophysiology. 2005;94(1):327–337. doi: 10.1152/jn.00838.2004. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Avena NM, Rada P, Hoebel BG. Evidence for sugar addiction: behavioral and neurochemical effects of intermittent, excessive sugar intake. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews. 2007;32(1):20–39. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2007.04.019. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Bartels A, Zeki S. The neural basis of romantic love. Neuroreport. 2000;11(17):3829–3834. doi: 10.1097/00001756-200011270-00046. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Berry S. Addicted to love. Sydney Morning Herald. 2013 Apr 2; Accessed at: http://www.smh.com.au/lifestyle/life/addicted-to-love-20130401-2h2bz.html .
- Blum K, Chen LC, Giordano J, Borsten J, Chen TJH, Hauser M, Simpatico T, Femino J, Braverman ER, Barh D. The addictive brain: all roads lead to dopamine. Journal of Psychoactive Drugs. 2012;44(2):134–143. doi: 10.1080/02791072.2012.685407. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Blum K, Werner T, Carnes S, Carnes P, Bowirrat A, Giordano J, Berman MO, Gold M. Sex, drugs, and rock ‘n’ roll: hypothesizing common mesolimbic activation as a function of reward gene polymorphisms. Journal of Psychoactive Drugs. 2012;44(1):38–55. doi: 10.1080/02791072.2012.662112. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Boorse C. What is disease? Humana Press; New York: 1997. A rebuttal on health; pp. 1–134. [ Google Scholar ]
- Burkett JP, Young LJ. The behavioral, anatomical and pharmacological parallels between social attachment, love and addiction. Psychopharmacology. 2012;224(1):1–26. doi: 10.1007/s00213-012-2794-x. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Caplan A. Denying autonomy in order to create it: the paradox of forcing treatment upon addicts. Addiction. 2008;103(12):1919–1921. doi: 10.1111/j.1360-0443.2008.02369.x. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Carnes PJ. Sexual addiction. In: Sadock S, editor. Comprehensive textbook of psychiatry. Lippincott, Williams & Wilkins; Philadelphia: 2005. [ Google Scholar ]
- Carson DS, Hunt GE, Guastella AJ, Barber L, Cornish JL, Arnold JC, Boucher AA, McGregor IS IS. Systemically administered oxytocin decreases methamphetamine activation of the subthalamic nucleus and accumbens core and stimulates oxytocinergic neurons in the hypothalamus. Addiction Biology. 2010;15:448–463. doi: 10.1111/j.1369-1600.2010.00247.x. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Curley B. DSM-V: major changes to addictive disease classifications. Recovery today online. 2010 Accessed at: http://www.recoverytoday.net/articles/143-dsm-v-major-changes-to-addictive-disease-classifications/
- Curtis JM. Elements of pathological love relationships. Psychological Reports. 1983;53:83–92. doi: 10.2466/pr0.1983.53.1.83. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Di Chiara G, Bassareo V, Fenu S, De Luca MA, Spina L, Cadoni C, Acquas E, Carboni E, Valentini V, Lecca D. Dopamine and drug addiction: the nucleus accumbens shell connection. Neuropharmacology. 47(1):227–41. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropharm.2004.06.032. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Earp BD, Sandberg A, Savulescu J. The medicalization of love. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics. 2015 doi: 10.1017/S0963180114000206. in press. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Earp BD, Sandberg A, Savulescu J. Brave new love: The threat of high-tech “conversion” therapy and the bio-oppression of sexual minorities. AJOB Neuroscience. 2014;5(1):4–12. doi: 10.1080/21507740.2013.863242. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Earp BD, Sandberg A, Kahane G, Savulescu J. When is diminishment a form of enhancement? Rethinking the enhancement debate in biomedical ethics. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience. 2014;8(12):1–8. doi: 10.3389/fnsys.2014.00012. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Earp BD, Sandberg A, Savulescu J. Natural selection, childrearing, and the ethics of marriage (and divorce): building a case for the neuroenhancement of human relationships. Philosophy & Technology. 2012;25(4):561–587. doi: 10.1007/s13347-012-0081-8. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Earp BD, Wudarczyk OA, Sandberg A, Savulescu J. If I could just stop loving you: Anti-love biotechnology and the ethics of a chemical breakup. American Journal of Bioethics. 2013;13(11):3–17. doi: 10.1080/15265161.2013.839752. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Esch T, Stefano GB. The neurobiology of love. Neuroendocrinology Letters. 2005;26(3):175–192. [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Esch T, Stefano GB. The neurobiology of pleasure, reward processes, addiction and their health implications. Neuroendocrinology Letters. 2004;25:235–51. [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Federal Bureau of Investigation Uniform crime reports, expanded homicide data table 10. 2011 Accessed at: http://www.fbi.gov/about-us/cjis/ucr/crime-in-the-u.s/2011/crime-in-the-u.s.-2011/tables/expanded-homicide-data-table-10 .
- Fisher HE, Brown LL, Aron A, Strong G, Mashek D. Reward, addiction, and emotion regulation systems associated with rejection in love. Journal of Neurophysiology. 2010;104(1):51–60. doi: 10.1152/jn.00784.2009. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Fisher HE, Aron A, Brown LL. Romantic love: a mammalian brain system for mate choice. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 2006;361(1476):2173–2186. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2006.1938. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Fisher HE. Why we love: the nature and chemistry of romantic love. Henry Holt; New York: 2004. [ Google Scholar ]
- Foddy B, Savulescu J. A liberal account of addiction. Philosophy, Psychology, and Psychiatry. 2010;17(1):1–22. doi: 10.1353/ppp.0.0282. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Foddy B. Addicted to food, hungry for drugs. Neuroethics. 2011;4(2):79–89. [ Google Scholar ]
- Frankfurt HG. The reasons of love. Princeton University Press; Princeton: 2004. [ Google Scholar ]
- Frascella J, Potenza MN, Brown LL, Childress AR. Carving addiction at a new joint? Shared brain vulnerabilities open the way for non-substance addictions. In: Uhl G, editor. Addiction reviews. New York Academy of Sciences; New York: 2010. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Fromm E. The art of loving. Harper & Brothers; New York: 1956. [ Google Scholar ]
- Griffin J. Well-being. Clarendon Press; Oxford: 1986. [ Google Scholar ]
- Heaton JP, Adams MA. Update on central function relevant to sex: remodeling the basis of drug treatments for sex and the brain. International Journal of Impotence Research. 2003;15(5):25–32. doi: 10.1038/sj.ijir.3901069. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Hyman S. The neurobiology of addiction: implications for voluntary control of behavior. The American Journal of Bioethics. 2007;7(1):8–11. doi: 10.1080/15265160601063969. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Insel TR. Is social attachment an addictive disorder? Physiology & Behavior. 2003;79(3):351–357. doi: 10.1016/s0031-9384(03)00148-3. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Kahane G, Savulescu J. The welfarist account of disability. In: Brownlee K, Cureton A, editors. Disability and disadvantage. Oxford University Press; Oxford: 2009. [ Google Scholar ]
- Kelley AE, Berridge KC. The neuroscience of natural rewards: relevance to addictive drugs. Journal of Neuroscience. 2002;22(9):3306–3311. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.22-09-03306.2002. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Kirsch P, Reuter M, Mier D, Lonsdorf T, Stark R, Gallhofer B, Vaitl D, Hennig J. Imaging gene-substance interactions: the effect of the DRD2 TaqIA polymorphism and the dopamine agonist bromocriptine on the brain activation during the anticipation of reward. Neuroscience letters. 2006;405(3):196–201. doi: 10.1016/j.neulet.2006.07.030. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Kovacs GL, Szontagh L, Balaspiri L, Hodi K, Bohus P, Telegdy G. On the mode of action of an oxytocin derivative (Z-Pro-D-Leu) on morphine-dependence in mice. Neuropharmacology. 1981;20:647–651. doi: 10.1016/0028-3908(81)90111-8. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Le Moal M, Koob GF. Drug addiction: pathways to the disease and pathophysiological perspectives. European Neuropsychopharmacology. 2007;17(6):377–393. doi: 10.1016/j.euroneuro.2006.10.006. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Lenoir M, Serre F, Cantin L, Ahmed SH. Intense sweetness surpasses cocaine reward. PLoS ONE. 2007;2(1) doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0000698. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0000698. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Levy N. Addiction is not a brain disease (and it matters) Frontiers in Psychiatry. 2013;4(24):1–7. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2013.00024. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Margolis J. O: the intimate history of the orgasm. Grove Press; New York: 2005. [ Google Scholar ]
- Mearns J. Coping with a breakup: negative mood regulation expectancies and depression following the end of a romantic relationship. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1991;60:327–334. doi: 10.1037//0022-3514.60.2.327. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- McGregor IS, Callaghan PD, Hunt GE. From ultrasocial to antisocial: a role for oxytocin in the acute reinforcing effects and long-term adverse consequences of drug use? British Journal of Pharmacology. 2008;154(2):358–368. doi: 10.1038/bjp.2008.132. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Nestler EJ. Is there a common molecular pathway for addiction? Nature Neuroscience. 2005;8(11):1445–1449. doi: 10.1038/nn1578. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Norville K, Sweeney ST, Elliott CJ. Postmating change in physiology of male drosophila mediated by serotonin (5-HT) Journal of Neurogenetics. 2010;24(1):27–32. doi: 10.3109/01677060903477601. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Parfit D. Reasons and persons. Oxford University Press; Oxford: 1984. [ Google Scholar ]
- Peele S, Brodsky A. Love and addiction. Taplinger; New York: 1975. [ Google Scholar ]
- Reynaud M, Karila L, Blecha L, Benyamina A. Is love passion an addictive disorder? The American Journal of Drug and Alcohol Abuse. 2010;36:261–267. doi: 10.3109/00952990.2010.495183. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Savulescu J, Earp BD. Neuroreductionism about sex and love. Think. 2014;13(38):7–12. doi: 10.1017/S1477175614000128. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Savulescu J, Sandberg A. Neuroenhancement of love and marriage: the chemicals between us. Neuroethics. 2008;1(1):31–44. [ Google Scholar ]
- Savulescu J. Autonomy, the good life, and controversial choices. In: Rhodes R, Francis LP, Silvers A, editors. The Blackwell guide to medical ethics. Blackwell Publishing; Oxford: 2007. pp. 17–37. [ Google Scholar ]
- Savulescu J. Autonomy, well-being, disease, and disability. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 2009;16(1):59–65. [ Google Scholar ]
- Small DM, Zatorre RJ, Dagher A, Evans AC, Jones-Gotman M. Changes in brain activity related to eating chocolate: From pleasure to aversion. Brain. 2001;124:1720–33. doi: 10.1093/brain/124.9.1720. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Sidgwick H. The methods of ethics. Macmillan; London: 1874/1962. [ Google Scholar ]
- Sussman S. Love addiction: definition, etiology, treatment. Sexual Addiction & Compulsivity: The Journal of Treatment & Prevention. 2010;17(1):31–45. [ Google Scholar ]
- Timmreck TC. Overcoming the loss of a love: preventing love addiction and promoting positive emotional health. Psychological Reports. 1990;66(2):515–528. doi: 10.2466/pr0.1990.66.2.515. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Volkow ND, Fowler JS, Wang GJ, Goldstein RZ. Role of dopamine, the frontal cortex and memory circuits in drug addiction: Insight from imaging studies. Neurobiology of Learning & Memory. 2002;78(3):610–624. doi: 10.1006/nlme.2002.4099. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Volkow ND, Fowler JS, Wang GJ, Swanson JM, Telang F. Dopamine in drug abuse and addiction: results of imaging studies and treatment implications. Archives of Neurology. 2007;64(11):1575–1579. doi: 10.1001/archneur.64.11.1575. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Volkow ND, Wang GJ, Fowler JS, Tomasi D, Telang F, Baler R. Addiction: decreased reward sensitivity and increased expectation sensitivity conspire to overwhelm the brain’s control circuit. Bioessays. 2010;32(9):748–755. doi: 10.1002/bies.201000042. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Wise RA. Neurobiology of addiction. Current Opinion in Neurobiology. 1996;6:243–251. doi: 10.1016/s0959-4388(96)80079-1. [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Wudarczyk OA, Earp BD, Guastella A, Savulescu J. Could intranasal oxytocin be used to enhance relationships? Research imperatives, clinical policy, and ethical considerations. Current Opinion in Psychiatry. 2013;26(5):474–484. doi: 10.1097/YCO.0b013e3283642e10. [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- View on publisher site
- PDF (87.4 KB)
- Collections
Similar articles
Cited by other articles, links to ncbi databases.
- Download .nbib .nbib
- Format: AMA APA MLA NLM
COMMENTS
Love is both a wonderful thing and a cunning evolutionary trick to control us. A dangerous cocktail in the wrong hands. Untitled (Portrait of a Man and a Woman) (1851), daguerreotype, United States. Courtesy the Art Institute of Chicago.
I believe that love can be a deadly drug because people feel that they need love in their lives. That without love they are just small and lonely. Love can be a dangerous because it plays with your mind and heart. It can make you do things that you would never do in your entire life.
Here are 10 examples of its negative potential: 1. By altering your consciousness, love can lead you to feel, and act, off-balance. The descriptive phrases “ falling in love” or “ head over heels...
In the world of Romeo and Juliet, love is not pretty or idealized—it is chaotic and dangerous. Throughout the play, love is connected through word and action with violence, and Romeo and Juliet ’s deepest mutual expression of love occurs when the “star-crossed lovers take their life.”
Writers, poets, and philosophers have attempted to define what it means to fall in love and how it comes to manifest itself for centuries, without much overall success or agreement. One highly...
In Romeo and Juliet by William Shakespeare the lovers share a love strewn with sorrow. Shakespeare develops the theme that love is dangerous through the conflict between the royal families and Romeo and Juliet’s impulsivity.
In his 1996 book Dangerous Love, Nigerian author Ben Okri delves into the complex and often perilous nature of love. Through a series of interconnected stories set in Lagos, Okri explores the ways in which love can bring both joy and pain, and how it can be both a source of liberation and a trap.
Strong beliefs in true love could be blinding you to both the good and bad in your partner, with sometimes toxic results. Old-fashioned romantics might have the wrong idea about love.
The enduring appeal of the play lies in its ability to resonate with the universal themes of love's power to transcend barriers, the inevitability of fate, and the tragic consequences of unchecked passions.
Although the exact nature of the relationship between love and addiction has been described in inconsistent terms throughout the literature, we offer a framework that distinguishes between a narrow view and a broad view of love addiction.